A Companion to the Political Culture of the Roman Republic. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: История
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119673590
Скачать книгу
Stubbe, working with the godly republican, Henry Vane, who had since 1656 been willing to countenance a two-tier citizenship with the godly in charge, took up the cudgels for a select senate, in direct dispute with Harrington. For Harrington, one of the flaws in the Roman Republic, which rendered it ‘unequal’ and therefore mortal, was the constitution of its senate. Senators holding office for life, or a senate which drew exclusively from a separate hereditary order, were fatal to the carefully orchestrated balance of his commonwealth, and he saw the Roman Senate as representing both problems. In addition, the popular assemblies were rigged in favour of wealthier inhabitants, so that ‘the first and second [property] classes may give the suffrage of the whole people’ (Harrington 1977: 731–732). For advocates of a powerful select senate, however, these apparently aristocratic elements of the Roman republican constitution were treated not as flaws but as models for a safely controllable republic in a time of desperate political instability and popular royalism. Stubbe argued that the Roman constitution demonstrated how a ‘counter-poyse’ could balance popular power: voting in the comitia centuriata was rightly determined by the ‘very unequal proportion’ of centuries made up of the elites. The powers of the Roman Senate, too, could offer a model to England: Stubbe conceded that legislative power at Rome was in the people, but emphasised that the Senate’s emergency powers could even ‘annul Lawes made by the People’, and ultimately argued ‘that as all the good government of that Republick, and all the grandeur was derived from the Senate, so the aforesaid Senate was a power in some cases co-ordinate, or rather Supreme to the People’ (Stubbe 1659: 73–74).

      3.6 Monarchism

      As we have seen, then, Rome was often used to think through the claims of popular and aristocratic government, and to grapple with the relationship between the many and the few. But Rome also came into play when considering the possibility of monarchical rule, whether Stuart or Cromwellian. Scholars dispute whether early modern republicanism should be defined by anti-monarchism (Worden 2002). Certainly not all of those who we tend to class as republicans were willing to exclude all forms of monarchy under all circumstances, and those who valued virtue more than institutional forms could invoke Aristotle’s criterion of superlative virtue to justify some forms of single rule – as Milton did for Cromwell’s rule in 1654 (Worden 2007: 257). If Rome was understood, in a Polybian vein, as a mixed polity composed of monarchy (the consuls), aristocracy (the Senate) and democracy (the popular assemblies) (see Chapter 8), then a quasi-monarchical role such as Cromwell’s might be justified by Roman precedent as part of a genuinely republican constitution. However, the consular role as such was a poor analogy for what actually happened in the 1650s, with Cromwell appointed for life and not elected. Thus, depictions of Cromwell as a Roman republican hero tended to sidestep the question of his exact constitutional role, while critics of Cromwell looked to the late Republic and the early emperors for exempla which proved that the extension of office – whether that of dictator or that of consul – could only portend the extinction of republican freedom. Even James Harrington, who defended a provision for temporary dictatorship (in the form of a committee) in times of emergency on the basis of Roman precedent and Machiavelli’s approval, was attempting to persuade Cromwell to relinquish his protectoral power rather than prolong it (Harrington 1977: 252–255).

      Attitudes to the Lord Protector – Oliver Cromwell, followed by his son Richard Cromwell – were sometimes expressed in rather veiled terms, and even praise could display considerable ambivalence (Norbrook 1999: 326–378). A ‘single person’ at the head of the state – and one who had achieved his place through military leadership – could be presented as a Roman republican hero. Such classicising representations of Cromwell, as Laura Knoppers has shown, made room for praise of Cromwell to be framed in republican terms (rather than terms which implicitly threatened the republic) in pre-Protectoral works such as Payne Fisher’s Irenodia Gratulatoria of 1652. Fisher ‘both links and dissociates’ Cromwell and Caesar in this Latin panegyric, invoking the comparison only to pointedly deflect it by contrasting Cromwell’s virtue and self-control with the empty applause of the Roman triumph and the avarice implied by Caesar’s violation of the treasury of Saturn (Knoppers 2000: 58–66). Similarly, Milton’s 1654 account of Cromwell’s triumph over his own passions and defeat of private interest and kingship gave the title of pater patriae (father of the fatherland), which he bestowed on him, a republican edge – perhaps reinforced by the disapproving reference elsewhere in the text to Catiline’s conspiracy, which Cicero had capitalised on to be granted that title himself. Cromwell remained civis maximus & gloriosissimus, dux publici consilii (the greatest and most glorious of our citizens, the director of public counsel), a republican citizen and leader rather than an Imperator (commander or emperor) in any sense but the military (Milton 1933: 222–223).

      3.7 English Republicans and Machiavelli

      The Roman Republic was not merely a static model for English republicans, but a historical exemplum, and they drew lessons from its development and eventual demise as well as from its institutions. In doing