A Companion to the Political Culture of the Roman Republic. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: История
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119673590
Скачать книгу
that Rousseau had carefully read), whose account of Roman politics both gave pride of place to the people as a political actor and showed the extent to which conflicts were conducive to, rather than destructive of, Roman republican freedom (see Chapter 2). This Machiavellian agonistic view of healthy free political societies should not be read as the embryo of a theory of revolution. However, it certainly contributed to casting a cloud of suspicion on the notion of peace or ‘civil tranquility’ (Rousseau 1762: 1.4, 50): ‘What really makes flourish the human race is less peace than freedom.’5

      4.4 Virtue

      Roman republican references, in the hands of Rousseau and his followers, could be sharp weapons turned against the smug champions of enlightened modern monarchies. Leaving it at that, however, would amount to missing the positive and constructive purpose these references fulfil.

      In his Discourse on political economy (DPE), Rousseau (1755: 53) defines ‘virtue’ restrictively as ‘this conformity of the particular will to the general’ and claims that one of the maxims of a legitimate government must be to ‘establish the reign of virtue’. Though using an ‘example’ is a less efficient means for the government than developing a ‘love of country’ (55) in citizens, Rousseau resorts to such examples in order to clarify his view of patriotism: ‘Let us dare to oppose Socrates even to Cato’ (56), since the former is ‘more of a philosopher… instructing some persons’, and the latter ‘more of a citizen…defending the state, freedom and the laws against the conquerors of the world’. Already perceptible is the difference both in the kind of goods (philosophical wisdom/political freedom) and in their scope (some/the citizenry). But Rousseau makes it still clearer: ‘the virtue’ of a contemporary Socrates ‘would make himself happy’; ‘a worthy emulator of Cato…would look after his own happiness in the happiness of all’. This difference ‘alone’, Rousseau concludes, ‘would settle the preference, for no one has ever made a people of sages, but it is not impossible to make a people happy’ (Rousseau 1755: 56, emphasis mine).

      As we can already see, Rousseau is here dissociating philosophical wisdom and political happiness, while bringing the latter closer to freedom. But in choosing Cato to establish this assessment, is Rousseau not assimilating happiness and virtue nevertheless, with philosophical Stoicism scoring over philosophical Socratism? It is true that what immediately follows suggests so, with Rousseau asking: ‘Do we want peoples to be virtuous? Let us begin by making them love their country’ (1755: 56; see Lepan 2002) and capable of this ‘sublime virtue’ (Rousseau 1755: 49, 61). At least three reasons militate against such an assimilation.

      First, this passage should be read in light of a fragment comparing Socrates and Cato (Rousseau 1972). The same opposition is constructed – ‘Socrates would have made them [i.e. the people] wise, Cato would have made them happy’ – but he also rephrases it with a twofold shift. One is general, subsuming both terms of the opposition under the heading of freedom; the other is specific, revealing the political standpoint from which Rousseau wants the difference to be assessed: while Socrates’ inward or philosophical freedom did not make him hostile to tyranny, ‘Cato abhorred tyranny for it was not enough for him to be free, he also wanted all citizens to be so’ (54, my emphasis). Rousseau startlingly expresses here the notion of republican freedom, which is already evident in a Letter to Voltaire in which he describes himself as ‘republican’ (Rousseau 1764: 842 n.), written to defend the general causes of ‘religion, freedom and justice’ in the aftermath of the troubles caused by the publication of Of Social Contract and Émile: as Tacitus knew, to love freedom as a ‘republican’ means to strive for the freedom for all. As a result, Rousseau’s rephrasing the opposition in terms of happiness in the DPE does not rule out, but on the contrary takes for granted, the intimate association of happiness and republican freedom.

      Is the safety of one citizen (le salut d’un citoyen) less the common cause than that of the whole state?… The safety of the particular is so tied to the public confederation that… this covenant (convention) would be dissolved by the law (le droit) if one single citizen should perish while he could be rescued. (57)

      The Romans distinguished themselves above all other peoples on earth by the consideration (égards) the government had for private individuals (particuliers), and by its scrupulous care to respect the inviolable rights of all the members of the state. There was nothing as sacred as the life of ordinary citizens. (58)

      Among the different Roman laws or institutions he refers to, the leges Porciae, known as the ‘stronghold of Roman liberty’ (Nicolet 1979: 430–432; Arena 2012: 41), are interpreted here as evidence of the important Roman republican concern for individual safety (see Diderot 1753: 489; 1774: 190 for the same reading of the Porcia laws; Ducos 1991: 59–61).

      The intellectual significance of this move can hardly be overestimated: not only do Roman republican references provide Rousseau with the adequate means for articulating what is arguably one of the strongest eighteenth-century defences of individual rights (Spitz 1995: Chapter 11), but they also illustrate one of the most important rules of legitimate government, namely that protecting individual rights is at the same time the main precondition of civic virtue and its prime raison d’être.

      4.5 The Republic of Letters

      In