A Companion to the Political Culture of the Roman Republic. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: История
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119673590
Скачать книгу
not just with examples of patriotic fortitude and valour, but with a language which could evoke such Roman virtues even without explicit mention of Rome (on rhetoric, see Chapter 32; on ancient accounts, see Part II). This belief in a distinctively Roman matrix of virtue and valour was widespread enough to be found in texts or speeches which fell well outside the bounds of republican discourse. But for republicans, the cultural pervasiveness of these notions, along with their association with the greatest of the ancient republics, meant that the language of Roman valour and virtue was enormously useful. Against royalists emphasising the virtues of monarchy and of obedience to it, republicans could invoke a different model of virtue, but one with enormous cultural clout. Republicans could thus redescribe behaviour that royalists saw as unruly or rebellious as Roman valour in the cause of liberty. Thus John Milton, on the eve of the restoration of the monarchy, mourned the fact that the English people were apparently about to squander their early republican achievements, which had displayed ‘a spirit in this nation no less noble and well fitted to the liberty of a Comonwealth, then in the ancient Greeks or Romans’ (Milton 1980: 356). In Milton’s works the language of Roman virtue was pushed in a distinctively Ciceronian direction, not erasing its martial character, but emphasising that even the virtue of fortitudo, or courage, was not always martial, and that it was not war itself, but the certamen virtutis gloriosissimum atque pulcherrimum (the trial of virtue most fair and most glorious) and studium libertatis (zeal for liberty) which motivated the Greeks and Romans to expel their tyrants (Milton 1933: 6–7; Dzelzainis 1995). Even where Rome was not mentioned by name, in Milton’s Latin writings the use of the terms found in Ciceronian and other encomia of the Roman Republic and its defenders gave a Roman flavour to his republicanism. At the start of the Second Defence Milton credited the civium virtus eximia, magnitudo animi and constantia of the English (the effulgent virtue of its citizens…their magnanimity and steadfastness) with liberating the res publica (Commonwealth): it is hard to read these Latin phrases without Roman exempla in mind (Milton 1933: 2–3).

      3.4 The Constitutional Discussion

      Republicans analysed the constitution of the Roman Republic as well as invoking its spirit. Constitutional thought was often not at the forefront of English republicanism in this period, whether because existing constitutional arrangements could not easily be challenged (especially by those writing in support of the government), or because for some republican authors the spirit of republicanism was more important and urgent than its precise form. Nonetheless, Rome offered guidance on the principles which should animate a successful republic, starting with the location of sovereignty itself.

      James Harrington, too, argued that the people at Rome were sovereign – ‘as appears by the ancient style of their covenants or laws: censuere patres, iussit populus [the fathers resolved, the people commanded]’ (Harrington 1977: 166) – and took that as grounds for describing Rome as a popular state. Rome was one of the founts of ancient prudence which guided his imagining of an ideal ‘equal commonwealth’. However, ancient prudence was not a neutral term in Harrington’s vocabulary; it essentially meant the politics of commonwealths rather than monarchies – even mixed monarchies such as England with its two Houses of Parliament. Harrington did not simply reject the ancient ideal of mixed constitutions outright. Indeed, he appealed to it in justifying his own complex balanced constitution and suggested – following Polybius – that Rome was one example of a mixed government. Ridiculing Hobbes’s denial of the existence of mixed governments, Harrington asked which of the simple forms of government could have been senatus populusque Romanus (the Senate and people of Rome) (Harrington 1977: 163). However, in spite of this early defence of mixed government, Harrington rested his theory on foundations which ultimately led him in a rather different direction. Harrington classified his ideal commonwealth of Oceana and the ancient commonwealths – as far as he could – as popular governments or democracies. Popular government was the only viable form for a polity when the balance of landholding was popular; to ensure that the commonwealth was viable in perpetuity, it had to be equal, preserving the balance of land through an agrarian law and ensuring that a system of rotation prevented an oligarchy of the powerful from forming. The Roman Republic was a popular government, but it fell short of being equal in both these senses, and that led to its downfall.