Kant. Andrew Ward. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Andrew Ward
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Философия
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781509551125
Скачать книгу
formed, from any experience; it is, rather, a concept that we possess independently of experience. Such concepts may well be applied to what can be experienced, although this is not an essential feature of an a priori concept. What is essential is that an a priori concept is a concept that we possess independently of any experience.

      Just as there can be a priori concepts, so there can be a posteriori ones.As one would expect, these are dependent (at least in part) upon experience. Our concept of copper is a posteriori, since it requires experience in order to be formed.

      We can now examine Kant’s division of judgments into three categories. In particular, we need to ask how each type of judgment can be established.

      (1) Analytic a priori judgments. Since every analytic judgment depends, for Kant, only on the meaning of the terms involved, such a judgment can always be established by determining that the meaning of the predicate term is included in the subject term, i.e. by showing that the denial of the judgment is self-contradictory. All analytic judgments, therefore, must be a priori, since no recourse to experience is necessary to establish them. (The subject and the predicate terms themselves may require experience in order to be formed, as in the case of ‘bachelor’ and ‘unmarried’. But the point is that once the meaning of the subject and the predicate terms is understood – whether they are themselves expressive of a priori or a posteriori concepts – there can be no need to consult experience in order to establish any analytic judgment. All that is required is an analysis of the meaning of the terms involved, together with the application of the principle of contradiction.)

      (2) Synthetic a posteriori judgments. These judgments are not analytically true, and are established by recourse to experience. There is clearly no difficulty in grasping how there can actually be such judgments. When a judgment cannot be determined in virtue of the meaning of the terms involved (and so is synthetic), it is an entirely familiar, and frequently a successful, procedure to seek to establish it a posteriori, i.e. by consulting experience. The judgment ‘All men are mortal’ is synthetic. It is also a posteriori, since it is established on the basis of past experience and induction (the universality claimed is only comparative). Note that all empirical judgments – judgments that make recourse to experience – are synthetic a posteriori. For if a judgment requires experience to be established (and so is a posteriori), it cannot be true merely in virtue of the meaning of the terms involved. Hence, it must be synthetic as well as a posteriori.

      (3) Synthetic a priori judgments. These are not analytically true yet require to be established independently of experience. Undoubtedly, it is this class of judgments in which Kant is principally interested. Now although such judgments are not ruled out ab initio (as are analytic a posteriori judgments), it is not at all obvious how any claimed synthetic a priori judgment could ever be established. In order to establish it, we evidently cannot consult experience, otherwise the judgment would not be a priori but a posteriori. On the other hand, we plainly cannot seek to establish the judgment merely on the basis of the meaning of the terms involved. Only analytic judgments can be established in this manner; and ex hypothesi we are interested in establishing a synthetic, not an analytic, judgment. But if the judgment cannot be established either in virtue of the meaning of the terms involved or by consulting experience, how is a connection between the subject and the predicate of any supposed synthetic a priori judgment to be established?

      Let us return to our earlier example. In the judgment ‘Every change of state must have a cause’, the concept cause is not included in the concept change of state.As Hume has shown, the denial of the judgment is not self-contradictory. So the judgment cannot be analytic. It is, therefore, a synthetic judgment. But the judgment also claims necessity (‘must have a cause’) as well as strict universality (‘Every change of state’). So it is an a priori judgment: one that cannot be dependent on experience. But how can we hope to establish a genuine connection between the subject and the predicate in such a judgment?

      It is, of course, just this question, when generalized to include all the axioms and principles of pure mathematics and natural science, as well as the significant judgments in metaphysics, that not only awoke Kant from his dogmatic slumbers but led him to propose his own revolutionary response (his Copernican revolution). Putting the point in his own terminology, Kant holds that all the fundamental judgments in these areas are synthetic a priori. Accordingly, the key question for him is to discover how such judgments can ever be established.

      But now it may be objected that the claim that pure mathematics and natural science are bodies of synthetic a priori judgments is far from obvious. In his Introduction to the First Critique, Kant goes to considerable lengths to convince his readers that the axioms or principles of both disciplines are genuine instances of synthetic a priori judgments.

      Mathematics