Kant. Andrew Ward. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Andrew Ward
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Философия
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781509551125
Скачать книгу
by Kant/Kemp-Smith (second edition) and to Cambridge University Press for permission to quote from Immanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason edited by Mary J. Gregor and with an introduction by Andrews Reath, 1997.

Part I Critique of Pure Reason

      I want to introduce Kant’s philosophical approach in the Critique of Pure Reason – also known as the First Critique – by looking at what he took to be Hume’s sceptical stance on causation, and how, in general terms, he sought to overcome it. When Kant himself set out the main threads of his argument in his own introductory essay on the First Critique, unappealingly entitled Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics that will be able to Present itself as a Science, it was his reaction to Hume’s scepticism about causation that he particularly singled out. He did so not only because Hume’s scepticism awoke him from his dogmatic slumbers, but, more crucially, because it gave him the hint of the correct approach to philosophical problems:

      Since Locke’s and Leibniz’s Essays, or rather since the beginning of Metaphysics as far as the history of it reaches, no event has occurred which could have been more decisive in respect of the fate of this science than the attack that David Hume made on it. He brought no light into this kind of knowledge, but he struck a spark at which a light could well have been kindled, if it had found a receptive tinder and if the glow had been carefully kept up and increased. (Prol, Preface; 4:257).

      But if experience will not do the trick, how could the causal principle be proved? The only alternative, Hume contended, is to show that it is true in virtue of the meaning of the terms involved. If the meaning of ‘event’ includes in it ‘having a cause’, then, indeed, we can justifiably assert that every event must have a cause. (Just as we can justifiably assert that every bachelor must be unmarried. In this latter case, the mere analysis of the subject term ‘bachelor’ and the predicate term ‘unmarried’ reveals that to deny the judgment would be self-contradictory.) But, as Hume argued, there simply is no such connection of meaning between the subject and the predicate terms in the principle ‘Every event must have a cause.’ To deny it is not self-contradictory. In Kantian terminology, the principle is not analytically true.

      Since the principle is not analytically true, and, as Hume contended, this is the only acceptable way to prove that a judgment holds with strict universality and necessity, he concluded that our belief in the principle is unjustified.

      Why, then, do we believe it? Here, Hume gives a psychological answer. It is the constant occurrence, throughout our past experience, of similar changes of state, under the same circumstances, that has led to our belief that the principle is justified. Far from the belief arising from, or being provable by, our rational faculties, it is merely the product of our enlivened imagination. In particular, the necessity that we ascribe to the principle is merely a ‘subjective necessity’ or feeling of inevitability (arising from our experience of past constant conjunctions), and not an objective necessity (not a requirement, discernible in the objects or in our judgment about the objects, that nature is uniform). Accordingly, so far as reason or understanding is concerned, our experience of nature could have been entirely chaotic. Moreover, there is absolutely no rational ground for supposing that our experience – even granting that it has, in fact, been as regular as clockwork up to now – might not turn random, acausal, at any moment in the future. The supposition that the future course of events will resemble the past cannot even be shown to be probable, let alone necessary.

      But he disagreed with Hume about the status of the general principle that every event, or change of state, in nature must have a cause. Although he thought that Hume was correct to maintain that this principle is not analytically true, he rejected what he took to be Hume’s conclusion from this observation: namely, that the principle cannot be justified.

      How, though, can the causal principle legitimately carry necessity and universality, if not in virtue of the meaning of the terms involved?

      To understand Kant’s answer to this question is to be well on the way to understanding many of the central ideas in the Critique of Pure Reason. He was not exaggerating when he claimed that Hume had struck a spark which, if carefully kindled, would produce a new light on metaphysics. For Kant thought that the status of the causal principle could be generalized to take in not only all the leading judgments in metaphysics, but also all the fundamental judgments in two areas of what he saw as unquestionably genuine repositories of knowledge of objects: namely, pure mathematics and pure natural science (pure natural science forms the non-empirical basis of Newtonian physics). And this thought, in turn, led him to conclude that there must be something wrong with Hume’s scepticism. Since, as he affirmed, there certainly are two areas where we can find examples of judgments which, while not analytically true, hold with necessity and universality, viz. in pure mathematics and pure natural science, what is required is not a wholesale dismissal of all such knowledge claims, but an investigation of how such judgments can be true, in those two areas where they clearly exist.