Kant. Andrew Ward. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Andrew Ward
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Философия
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781509551125
Скачать книгу
made by sensations, viz. the body’s colour, texture, etc.; and if we also subtract anything that the understanding may contribute, viz. features like force and permanence; we still possess the capacity to draw the shape or outline of that appearance – or indeed of any possible outer appearance – even though no actual appearance is now being apprehended. Our capacity to draw the form – the extension and shape – of any possible outer appearance, even when no appearance is actually present to the senses, shows that there must exist in the mind the capacity to form pure intuitions. This further supports Kant’s claim that our sensibility must itself possess the form or forms necessary for apprehending and relating together the matter of any appearance. With respect to the form of an outer appearance, he says that ‘extension and figure . . . belong to pure intuition, which even without any actual object of the senses or sensation, exists in the mind a priori as a mere form of sensibility’ (A 21/B 35).

      The mind, then, has a faculty of sensible receptivity (sensibility) through which it has the power to form pure intuitions. We have seen this power illustrated by the above thought-experiment; and Kant will later claim that it is crucially at work in the construction of geometrical figures and arithmetical products. He holds that the mind possesses two forms of sensible intuition: that by which extension and figure are represented is called ‘outer intuition’, and that by which succession and the simultaneous are represented is called ‘inner intuition’. It is because the mind possesses these two a priori forms of sensible intuition that it can also become conscious of appearances – that is, of empirical intuitions.When the object which exists independently of the mind (the thing in itself, or transcendental object) affects our sensibility, we become conscious of appearance(s) in outer or inner intuition: in other words, we have an outer or inner empirical intuition.

      When Kant specifically turns to discuss space and time, rather than the forms of our intuition, he immediately signals that what concerns him is how space and time are related to our outer and inner intuitions: ‘What then are space and time? Are they real existences? Are they only determinations or relations of things, yet such as would belong to things even if they were not intuited? Or are space and time such that they belong only to the form of intuition, and therefore to the subjective constitution of the mind, apart from which they could not be ascribed to anything whatsoever?’ (A 23/B 37).

      Three views of space and time are on offer here; and it seems clear that Kant regards them as exhaustive. According to the first, the Newtonian (or absolute) view, space and time exist not only independently of being perceived, but independently of any objects (understood as things in themselves) in space or time. This is the view being referred to when it is asked if space and time are real existences. According to the second, Leibnizian (or relational), view, space and time do exist independently of being perceived, but do not exist independently of things in themselves. Space and time are merely the relations holding between things in themselves, which we confusedly perceive by means of sensations in our minds. This is the view that is being referred to when it is asked if space and time are only relations or determinations of things (in themselves), yet such as would belong to things (in themselves) even if they were not intuited.

      The Metaphysical and Transcendental Expositions of space

      As regards the Metaphysical Exposition of space, its method is to begin with certain very general thoughts about space (e.g. that each subject thinks that there is only one, and not a multiplicity of, spaces in which he can place objects), and then to show that such thoughts can only be justified if space is a pure (or a priori) intuition. Kant presumably takes it that the proponents of the opposing views of space acknowledge that any acceptable view must accommodate these ideas. I shall follow the text of the B edition, which is divided into four arguments. (The A edition has five arguments; but the third is replaced in the B edition by the Transcendental Exposition.)

       Metaphysical Exposition

      The first two arguments of the Metaphysical Exposition are designed to show that we have an a priori, and not an empirical, conception of space.

      Argument 1: In the opening argument, Kant considers whether our conception of space can have been arrived at from a number of outer experiences, viz. from an empirical consciousness of certain relations holding between the contents of sensations, relations like alongside of, at a distance from, and so on. However, if we had formed our concept of space from outer experiences, it must be possible to think of these experiences independently of thinking of the concept which has allegedly been acquired by means of them. For example, our empirical concept table can be formed by first having sensed instances of the concepts leg, flat top, etc., and acquiring the concept table therefrom. This is possible because the former concepts can be acquired from sensations without presupposing the latter concept. But, Kant contends, we cannot conceivably have built up our concept of space empirically by means of first observing certain relations between outer appearances. For, in order to be empirically conscious of outer appearances as e.g. alongside of or at a distance from each other, we must already have set the manifold of apprehended sensations (out of which the appearances are constituted) together in space.