A Companion to the Political Culture of the Roman Republic. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: История
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119673590
Скачать книгу
of the Arts are but ‘despots of literature’ keeping men of letters in their ‘dependence’ (d’Alembert 1753a: 403). Because of men’s fondness for superiority, mécènes (‘patrons’, derived from ‘Maecenas’) tend to assimilate the granting of a benefit with ‘an act of sovereignty which one abuses to put some unfortunate under one’s dependence’ (397). This kind of servitude breeds servile attitudes and fosters hypocrisy and self-censure. But more seriously, its peculiar effect is to make the very blessings given by benefactors ‘dreadful’, ‘sometimes humiliating’, and to ‘communicate to the soul a debasement that imperceptibly degrades ideas’ (398). In a striking move, d’Alembert uses the republican commonplace of the good master to make a frontal attack on them, taking the mécènes’ despotism as just another manifestation of the more general scourge of tyranny:

      Much has been written, and rightly so, against the ungrateful, but we have left the benefactors in peace, and this is a missing chapter in the story of Tyrants. (397)

      These relationships of dependence, he concludes, could not be more distant from what is expected in a republic: ‘the term Republic of Letters is quite ill devised: nothing is less republican than [the mécènes’] line of conduct and their ways of behaviour towards their fellow creatures’ (402). As d’Alembert makes clear, by turning Juvenal’s cutting remark about the passivity of the Roman people under emperors into a pious republican hope, the most terrible effect of this predicament is the incapacity of men of letters to claim freedom:

      The Romans used to say: ‘bread and circuses’ [Juv. 10.80]; how desirable would it be that all men of letters had the courage to say: ‘bread and freedom!’ (399)

      Further reinforced by d’Alembert’s immediate specification – that the freedom in question is ‘not only in their persons but also in their writings’ (ibid.) – the political message of the analogy is very clear: such a freedom could not stop at the boundaries of the Republic of Letters. The charges against the despotic society of the men of letters cannot but spread to society at large. True, when he then states his most radical contention – ‘only the democratic form [of government] was appropriate to such a state as the Republic of Letters, which lives only on its liberty’ (403–404) – he carefully specifies that the literary society is not literally, but only metaphorically, a state. Yet the question that inevitably arises, in turn, is whether the democratic (i.e. republican) Republic of Letters could exist under the French monarchy. For the power of the mécènes, direct interlocutors of men of letters, is far from being socially and politically metaphorical: mécènes are masters, nobles attached to the court, and d’Alembert’s wish that the Republic of Letters should unite together, hopefully to gain some degree of safety, is desperate and should not be taken too seriously. That great geniuses have nevertheless contributed to the advancement of learning and sciences, despite the ‘spirit of despotism’ reigning in some ‘famous academies’, is the exception proving the general rule that ‘in a despotic state, the virtues of the citizen are a fool’s virtues’ (403).

      Therefore, d’Alembert’s conclusion seems to be that no Republic of Letters – however metaphorical this republic may be – will ever be possible except for free men living in a free republic tout court.

      4.6 Commerce and Corruption

      Still, one might say, the interest that enlightened philosophes had in Roman republican freedom does not mean that eighteenth-century republicans themselves, fascinated as they were by ancient models, were able to adjust their ideals to the inescapable realities of modern society. The conflict between wealth (or commerce) and virtue, in eighteenth-century France, has in Rousseau’s first Discourse (1748: 3.3) its quintessential formulation: ‘Ancient politics were continually talking about mores and virtue; ours talk about nothing but commerce and money.’

      However, contrary to the deep-rooted view that neoclassical political piety for Roman virtue necessarily implies a condemnation of commerce as such (Spitz 1995: Chapter 7; Baker 1990: 134, on Saige), what is deemed dangerous for nations is more precisely to make ‘commerce the only foundation of their strength’ (Saige 1770: 95 n. 11, emphasis mine; for Rousseau, see Spitz 2000: 22–26; Bachofen 2007). This claim is voiced in one important republican text of eighteenth-century France: Cato, or Conversation upon freedom and political virtues (1770) by Guillaume-Joseph Saige. In the twilight of the Roman Republic, Cato, Cicero and Favonius are conversing, and Saige’s notes in the margin reveal the contemporary diagnostic function of this conversation. In his first note commenting on ‘Cato’s’ account of the loss of Roman freedom, Saige (1770: 83 n. 1) not only relativises the gap separating the ancient Roman Republic and contemporary European states, he also contests that peoples have, on the whole, gained from the substitution of commerce for conquest as the main political goal – this replacement, he argues, provides us ‘the story of the progress of corruption in Modern nations.’

      However, two misunderstandings should be dismissed at this point. First, although republicans usually denounce commerce and inequality as the corrupting forces of the mores of free peoples (see Rousseau 1750a: 19 sq.; Saige 1770: 11; Mably 1776: 16), their primary concern is not to make an austere republic of strictly equally poor and virtuous citizens come true, but to curb the growth of excessive wealth inequality, and thus of the dominating power, that inevitably follows such an unbridled pursuit of riches. Thus, while what makes the ‘progress of corruption’ dreadful is the growth of ‘base passions’ (Saige 1770: 11, see 8), these vices themselves are above all condemned for political motives: ambition and avarice are identified as ‘evils’ because they induce men to forfeit their independence for whatever these passions present as better goods. Mably (1758: 109–110, 185) concludes his similar account of the growth of luxury resulting from wealth inequality: ‘Here is Roman history.’ As Rousseau (1762: 2.11, 91) so neatly put this republican concern – having just claimed that ‘the greatest good of all’ and the ‘goal of all systems of legislation’ is ‘freedom and equality’ – ‘No citizen should be wealthy enough to be able to buy another, and no citizen poor enough to be forced to sell himself’ (see 1762, 3.15, 133; 1754: 123). This well-worn theme, which Saige (1770: 62–64) also illustrates from Roman history, will inspire variations from late eighteenth-century French republicans (Buonarroti 1828: 9–12).

      The second mistaken inference would construe Saige’s doubt about the alleged benefit of the substitution of commerce for conquest as exposing him to d’Holbach’s objection that Roman virtue mainly amounted to violent infringement of the most ‘sacred rights of peoples’ (d’Holbach 1776: vol.1, 89, 126). Far from eulogising the virtues of warlike societies and proposing a return to the ancient aggressive politics of conquest, Saige claims the Romans lost their freedom only because Heaven punished their ‘ambition’, which led them to ‘violate’ the peoples’ ‘rights of nature’, being ‘enslaved’ by this imperialist politics spreading domination all over the world (Saige 1770: 14–17, 32; see Mably 1758: 221).

      4.7 The Revolution

      Assessing the role and function of Roman republican thinking in the revolutionary era is an immensely complex task, if only because most of the political thinkers of the Revolution were at the same time its main protagonists. As a result, the leisured commerce with the ancients that allowed prerevolutionary authors to elaborate subtle, oblique or convoluted critiques of monarchy was obviously not available.

      The task is further complicated by the widely divergent assessments of the extent and meaning of the presence of Rome in the revolutionary period. On the one hand, it is