Thus, in a landmark US Supreme Court case in the early 1940s, a Jehovah’s witness was accused of using ‘fighting words’ – that is, words that provoke an immediate and often violent reaction in the listener – against a police officer. The Court ruled that ‘such utterances are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and morality’ (Chaplinsky v New Hampshire 1942). It is worth noting that in all such cases the harm is relatively short term and directed at specific individuals, and thus easy to assess within Mill’s consequentialist framework. Where harms are longer term and more diffuse, they raise, among other issues, questions about the responsibility of the speaker (Ten 1980), as we shall see in later chapters, when we discuss hate speech and pornography.
Mill’s case for free speech has been attacked on various grounds. One common criticism is that he proposes an over-intellectualised model of free speech, in which the social world is narrowly represented as a seminar room populated by earnest searchers for truth (Haworth 1998, pp. 24–32; Barendt 2005, pp. 9–10). But how about, for example, football chants, racist jokes, picketing strikers, or graffiti that stake out a gang’s territory (see McKinnon 2006, pp. 123–4)? This list might suggest that fewer things engage our deliberative capacities than Mill thinks. But perhaps more is covered by the truth discovery argument than appears at first glance. Perhaps football chants bring home to third parties how football is a ‘way of life’ for diehard supporters. Likewise, racist jokes are offensive and sometimes hateful, but they also tell us something about people’s attitudes towards race and ethnicity – and these views may be called out and contested. The ‘Fuck the Draft’ slogan in protest against the Vietnam war, a slogan that the Supreme Court defended as protected speech in Cohen v California (1971), may have helped to stimulate debate about the ethics of that war among those who saw it (see Barendt 2005, p. 10).
A further issue is that Mill seems to rely on an overly optimistic view of the likely consequences of free speech. Permissive public debate may result not in human progress, as measured by the discovery of truth and the development of our deliberative capacities, but in the rise and spread of extremist and other harmful views, with potentially catastrophic consequences for liberal democracy. Nazi Germany, for example, emerged from the thoroughly liberal Weimar Republic, and there are many recent examples of populism and far-right extremism in Europe, the United States, India and elsewhere, all spreading through a culture of free speech. Populist movements are often marked by the phenomenon of groupthink and a culture of intolerance; they do not consist of citizens who dispassionately think through the issues for themselves (and the same may be true to some extent of liberal regimes, too). Of course, whether speech should be limited in order to protect people’s rights and other interests is a large and much contested question, as we will see in detail in later chapters. But Mill’s view is particularly susceptible to the problem of the spread of harmful speech, and this is for two reasons.
First, unlike the autonomy and democracy arguments (which we will consider in a moment), Mill’s future-oriented consequentialist approach tells us that the value of free speech lies in its results, and more specifically in its positive effect on enlightened human progress. If this does not happen, if a positive effect is not registered, his theory falters. Second, as a utilitarian interested in human happiness, Mill seemingly should be concerned with other sources of human utility besides the achievement of better justified views and opinions. The fear, insecurity, discrimination and sometimes violence that vulnerable ethnic, religious or sexual minorities suffer as a result of hate speech significantly undermine the well-being of these groups; surely they, too, should count when it comes to assessing the consequences of freedom of speech? Conversely, racist, Islamophobic, anti-Semitic, homophobic and other forms of harmful speech probably serve group solidarity and the identity formation of their illiberal authors, but should not these, too, count as sources of well-being, in the eyes of the consistent utilitarian? If so, Mill’s consequentialist approach to free speech may seem less liberal than it appears at first glance.
Yet very often Mill is correct: the best way to combat false or harmful speech is, frequently, with more speech. Few of us think that people who deny the reality of human-caused climate change, or maintain that essential vaccines spread harmful illnesses, or argue that the COVID-19 pandemic was caused by 5G mobile phone masts1 should be actively censored by the state or by social media, although there may be a case for not giving them a prominent platform (e.g. on television). To that extent, most of us are good Millians: we think that false speech should be addressed with reason and evidence rather than silenced.
Free speech and autonomy
Autonomy involves a person’s governing her life according to her own judgement of what is best. It is opposed to a state in which some other agents usurp or thwart that judgement and direct the person’s life themselves. Such agents might be individuals (e.g. a slave owner, or a controlling husband who runs his wife’s life), groups (e.g. a religious hierarchy that directs every aspect of its adherents’ lives) or the state, which has the capacity coercively to require that citizens live in a certain way. Although there are affinities between autonomy and Mill’s ideal of individuality, the relationship between autonomy and free speech is more complex than in Mill’s truth-based account, for at least two reasons. First, it has been proposed in different ways by different contemporary writers; second, we need to attend more carefully to the distinctions between deontological and consequentialist models and between speaker- and audience-based views. A further distinction is between formal and substantive theories of autonomy (Baker 2011, pp. 253–4). Substantive autonomy is a character ideal – namely the ideal of self-government, which a person may realise in her life. Formal autonomy implies that third parties respect a person’s right to conduct her life according to her own best judgement.
Formal autonomy may be speaker-based or audience-based – that is, based on respect for a person’s capacity to express her views or on respect for an audience’s right to hear everyone’s view – but, either way, it is deontological rather than consequentialist in character. It implies that third parties are prevented from interfering in individuals’ lives (in our case, by having their speech limited), when they may want to do so for reasons of their own or for paternalistic ones – for example if they think that they could improve people’s lives by preventing them from accessing material they consider morally reprehensible. The only valid reason for interfering with a person’s formal autonomy, on this argument, is to protect the formal autonomy of another when that person would otherwise fail to respect it herself. (Here there is a clear affinity with Mill’s harm principle.)
Since we certainly need speech (ours and others’) in order to govern our own lives, the way autonomy can ground a defence of free speech is clear. A number of free speech theorists have adopted this strategy. One of the foremost American legal commentators on free speech, the late C. Edwin Baker (1997, 2011), proposed a speaker-based view that emphasises how (substantive) autonomy involves disclosing one’s own beliefs to a social world we share with others. Respect for autonomy, for Baker, ‘requires that each person must be permitted to be herself and to present herself [to others]. She must be permitted to act in and sometimes affect the world by at least some means, in particular by trying to persuade or criticize others’ (Baker 1997, p. 992). Respect for free speech, as part of respect for autonomy, protects people’s capacity to interact with one another on their own terms.
In another influential version of the argument, the late American legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin argued for a ‘right to moral independence’, which closely resembles respect for the formal autonomy of speakers