Free Speech. Jonathan Seglow. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Jonathan Seglow
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Афоризмы и цитаты
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781509526482
Скачать книгу
position for hate speech in the next chapter.)

      In his book Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech, the legal theorist Cass Sunstein defends another democracy-based argument for free speech by drawing an explicit distinction between ‘upper tier’ (high-value) speech, which contributes to public deliberation, and ‘lower tier’ speech, which does not. The upper tier category is capacious: apart from overtly political speech, it includes artistic, literary and cultural critique and broader social commentary (Sunstein 1993, pp. 148–53). Upper tier speech merits especially strong protection – that is, not just through viewpoint neutrality but also through the more encompassing content neutrality, which forbids governments from regulating speech merely on the grounds that it covers contentious topics, regardless of the view that is expressed on them. Thus, if a company forbade its employees to post any political views on social media, it would violate the constraint of content neutrality. Only content-neutral restrictions on the time, place and manner in which one expresses oneself may on occasion be justified at the level of upper tier speech. Thus it might be legitimate, for example, for a company to bar employees from posting political views on social media during work hours.

      The lower tier category consists of all other speech, including commercial speech (e.g. product descriptions, advertising), scientific speech, unlicensed medical and legal advice, depictions of violence in the media, defamation, hate speech, at least some pornography (some of which might also be political, as we shall see in Chapter 5), criminal speech such as bribery, insider trading, perjury, and threats of injury. This is a slightly confusing category, because it includes speech that is, actually or potentially, harmful in various ways and might even be better classified as conduct, not speech (e.g. threats and bribery), and speech that is not harmful but is not political either, even in the most expansive sense.

      Indeed the argument from democracy has an important advantage. In a liberal society there is always a presumption in favour of individual liberty, unless such liberty interferes with the interests of others. By helping us to distinguish between political speech (broadly interpreted) and non-political speech, the democracy argument explains why it may often be more permissible to regulate the latter than to regulate the former. As Robert Post notes, for example, an attack on the reputation of a public figure might fairly be seen as a contribution to political debate in a way in which defamation of a private individual is not (Post 2011, p. 480). The latter is a potential civil wrong. By contrast, the US Supreme Court upheld the former doctrine in New York Times Co. v Sullivan (1964), where that newspaper published an advert critical of the behaviour of the police in Alabama, which had arrested Martin Luther King Jr, as well as in other cases since then. In general, political speech may be more important to protect just by virtue of its connection with state power, and therefore with our other rights and freedoms.

      As we noted above, there is a clear affinity between Mill’s ideal of individuality and the ideal of personal autonomy. It is individualists who are most interested in truth in public affairs, and the search for truth, though a very social one – it must involve dialogue – is also one where individuals must exercise their independent critical powers by evaluating others’ views, by offering their own judgement to others, and by deciding what to believe. This is not the whole of autonomy – a person could conceivably exercise her deliberative capacities in the weighty public matters with which Mill was concerned, yet always follow the crowd in her personal life – but it is a substantial part of it. Conversely, the autonomous person has an interest in truth even in aspects of her life that are not public or political. A young woman contemplating a career in law or finance, for instance, has an interest in knowing which of those two professional fields is more marked by sex discrimination.