This Is Epistemology. J. Adam Carter. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: J. Adam Carter
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Афоризмы и цитаты
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119680376
Скачать книгу
evidence if it were real than we would if it were apparent. Disjunctivism seems to give us this, but the alternative views do not.

      2.56 Philosophers have raised a number of objections to the disjunctivist view, but we want to flag one particular objection that's important in an epistemological setting. The disjunctivist thinks that the experience we have when we perceive a tomato, say, is a relation between the perceiver and a tomato in which the tomato is something that the subject is directly aware of. They will grant that this isn't so when the subject has a hallucination, but insist that we shouldn't think of the conscious episode we have in hallucination as an “ingredient,” or part of what transpires in cases of perception. Let's suppose for a moment that this is so and that the underlying nature of the episodes taking place in perception and hallucination are fundamentally different. How is this epistemically helpful? By hypothesis, the perception is indistinguishable from the hallucination.

      2.57 We might put the worry this way:

      P1. Epistemic disjunctivism offers an interesting epistemic pay‐off only if it succeeds in establishing that the support provided by perception is better than the support provided by hallucination.

      P2. Perception is indistinguishable from hallucination.

      P3. If perception and hallucination are indistinguishable, then it's not the case that the support provided by perception is better than the support provided by hallucination.

      C1. Therefore, it's not the case that the support provided by perception is better than the support provided by hallucination.

      P4. Epistemic disjunctivism succeeds in establishing that the support provided by perception is better than the support provided by hallucination only if the support provided by perception is better than the support provided by hallucination.

      C2. Therefore, it's not the case that epistemic disjunctivism offers an interesting epistemic pay‐off.

      2.59 To understand Davidson's concerns, think about how you would typically go about offering a justification for a belief. You would offer something like an argument. A friend wants to know why you're convinced that it was Plum who killed Mustard; you might state a series of things that logically rule out alternative hypotheses (e.g. we know that it wasn't White, it wasn't Green, etc.). To play the role of supporting premises, the idea is that the supporting premise has to stand in some logical relationship to the conclusion (e.g. by ruling out the possibility that it is false). In the case of inferential reasoning, these premises are things that the thinker believes. These beliefs are, in turn, things that can be assessed for accuracy (i.e. they can be true or they can be false, correct or mistaken). In this respect, he thought that experiences differed from beliefs. Experiences, he thought, didn't stand in logical relations to beliefs in the way that other beliefs do. The belief that Plum alone killed Mustard logically entails that it wasn't someone else. A conscious experience does not logically entail anything.

      2.60 Putting this all together, we get an argument against the foundationalist view under consideration in this chapter. This argument is supposed to show that the beliefs that we form in response to perceptual experience are not non‐inferentially justified but would only be justified by support from further beliefs:

       A Davidsonian Argument against Foundationalism

      While an experience might cause a thinker to believe something, it does not give the thinker a reason to believe that thing. Nothing can give a thinker a reason to believe unless it stands in a logical relation to the thinker's beliefs. Only further beliefs do that. Experiences do not. An experience could only provide non‐inferential justification for our perceptual beliefs if they provided us with reasons for these beliefs. So, experience cannot provide non‐inferential justification for our perceptual beliefs.

      Where does this leave us? Is foundationalism finished?

      2.61 Let us now flag two controversial premises in this argument. A foundationalist might push back against one or both of these assumptions:

      No Content View: whereas beliefs have propositional contents that can be assessed for accuracy and inaccuracy and stand in logical relations to belief, experiences do not have propositional contents.

      If the foundationalist rejects the Premise Principle, they might grant that Davidson is right about what experiences are like but mistaken in thinking that this means that they cannot confer justification upon our beliefs. If the foundationalist rejects the No Content View, they might accept Davidson's assumptions about what kinds of things can justify while challenging Davidson's suggestion that experiences lack the properties needed to confer justification upon our beliefs.

      2.62 One can imagine a foundationalist taking issue with the Premise Principle. They might agree that in the case of inferential justification, we need the support of premises in the form of things that we believe for a belief to be justified. Perhaps one important difference between the case of non‐inferential justification and inferential justification is that in the former we don't need premises to justify our beliefs. When our experiences cause us to believe things, this gives us all the justification we need and it obviates the need for support from premises. We need supporting premises when we cannot determine something directly.

      2.64 If we reject the Premise Principle