This Is Epistemology. J. Adam Carter. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: J. Adam Carter
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Афоризмы и цитаты
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119680376
Скачать книгу
are as they appear to be, but the disposition can be overridden, and a subject like Macbeth can suspend judgment.

      2.21 It's important not to confuse the perceptual experience with the belief, and the case involving Macbeth nicely illustrates the potential gap between the two. Experiences, when taken at face value, explain why we believe what we do about our surroundings. If we don't distinguish experience from belief, experience could not play this role in psychological explanation of our opinions. Experiences, when taken at face value, arguably make certain beliefs reasonable or warranted, provided that a subject doesn't have good reason to doubt her senses. Experience could not play this normative role if an experience was just a belief. Belief, if you like, affirms that things are as they appear, thanks to experience. The experience itself, however, is not the affirmation.

      2.22 In the next two sections, we will address two important questions about the nature of experience. The first is a question about the objects of experience:

       Does experience ever provide us with direct contact with things in the external world?

      2.23 The second is about the similarities between experience and belief:

       Does experience represent things in the world in the way that our beliefs do?

      2.24 Our answers to these questions will help us decide whether liberal foundationalism is a viable view and might help us choose between Cartesian and moderate foundationalism.

      2.25 Are we ever directly aware of objects in the external world? Let's look at two contrasting views on the nature of perceptual experience.

      2.27 Second, on the rival indirect realist view, the answer is “no.” When we see a cup of coffee, say, we are aware of the cup but only indirectly. The IOA is something else. In experience, we are only ever directly aware of sense data, and no ordinary material object (OMO) is ever identical to sense data. The properties of the sense data determine the conscious character of your experience. It is by being directly aware of sense data that we're made indirectly aware of external objects (e.g. cups of coffee, tables, friends, etc.). Think of the way that, say, you're aware of a deer by being more immediately aware of its tracks, aware of incoming aircraft by being more immediately aware of blips on the radar screen, or aware of an intruder by being more immediately aware of the dog's barking. The indirect realist proposes that in every case of conscious experience (veridical – in other words, accurate – perceptual experience, illusion, hallucination) the IOA and its properties wholly determine what the conscious experience is like and then make us indirectly aware of external things if they are there and suitably related to us (e.g. by causing us to undergo certain experiences).

      2.29 The main point of difference between the naïve and indirect realists is over the truth of direct realism:

      Direct realism: it is possible for a subject to be immediately aware of an ordinary external object and its properties.

      The naïve realist thinks that the ordinary case of seeing a tomato shows us that direct realism is correct. The indirect realist thinks that the ordinary case of seeing a tomato shows us that it's false. This disagreement is a disagreement about the mind. It's not really an epistemological disagreement. (Notice that in stating the point of contention, we didn't use normative concepts [e.g. good/bad, right/wrong, reasonable/unreasonable] and didn't mention knowledge.) Why should it concern epistemologists?

      2.30 It should concern epistemologists because debates about what we can and cannot be immediately aware of interact with debates about we can and cannot rationally believe or know. It also interacts with more fine‐grained debates about how we can rationally believe or know (e.g. whether we need evidence over and above our experiences to believe certain things).

       An Argument against Liberal Foundationalism

      P1. If direct realism is false, we are never immediately aware of anything external to the mind.

      P2. If we are not immediately aware of something external to the mind, we cannot rely on experience alone to justifiably believe that such things exist or that such things have certain properties.

      C1. So, if direct realism is false, we cannot rely on experience alone to justifiably believe that such things exist or that such things have certain properties.

      P3. If liberal foundationalism is correct, we can rely on experience alone to justifiably believe that external things exist and have certain properties.

      C2. So, if direct realism is false, liberal foundationalism is mistaken.

      This kind of reasoning supports the idea that we cannot have justified beliefs from experience on its own to believe in things that we're only made aware of indirectly when we have an experience. Think about the blips on the radar screen. If you're aware of them but have no good independent reason to believe that these blips correlate with incoming aircraft, you cannot justifiably believe that aircraft are coming in just by seeing the blips. If you're aware of smoke but don't justifiably believe that smoke correlates with fire, you cannot justifiably believe that there's a fire.

      2.32 We don't take this kind of argument to be decisive. However, if this argument is sound, it's quite troubling. Not every foundationalist is a liberal foundationalist. There is a traditional foundationalist view that tries to account for knowledge about the external world inferentially. On such views, you might come to know via inference that a tomato exists or that it's red by basing these beliefs on more basic beliefs about