Museum Theory. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Изобразительное искусство, фотография
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119796558
Скачать книгу
time. And an order which organised the implied public – the white citizenries of imperialist powers – into a unity, representationally effacing divisions within the body politic in constructing a “we” conceived as the realisation and therefore just beneficiaries of the processes of evolution and identified as a unity in opposition to the primitive otherness of conquered peoples. (Bennett 1988, 92)

      The argument is a historical one. That is to say, it is an argument concerning the relations between the institutions and knowledges that constituted the exhibitionary complex at a particular phase in its development rather than one proposing a necessary and enduring set of such connections. I thus, in a further elaboration of the concept, argued that these connections constituted a historically specific political rationality which, like all such rationalities, generated its own internal contradictions and counterdynamics.3 Foucault argued that the prison was governed by a political rationality, which meant that it generated a demand for the reform of the offender that it could never meet, thus subjecting it to a perpetual criticism for failing to meet its objectives. Similarly, I argued, the exhibitionary complex’s evolutionary ordering of things and peoples generated a demand that it should offer a universally inclusive depiction of the history of Man as the culmination of the history of life on earth which it, too, proved unable to meet owing to the fact that the position of Man it constructed was always occupied by historically exclusive examples – usually white, bourgeois, male, and European or North American:

      Similarly, demands based on the principle of representational adequacy are produced and sustained by the fact that, in purporting to tell the story of Man, the space of representation shaped into being in association with the formation of the modern public museum embodies a principle of general human universality in relation to which, whether on the basis of the gendered, racial, class or other social patterns of its exclusions and biases, any particular museum display can be held to be inadequate and therefore in need of supplementation. (Bennett 1995, 91)

      There is another aspect to the political rationality of the museum which, like this first one, depends on a contrast with earlier exhibition forms. Where, as in the case of absolutist royal collections, exhibition served the purpose of making royal power manifest and where, accordingly, the pinnacle of representation governing the ordering of things was occupied by the prince or monarch, there could be no question of generating a principle of general inclusiveness from within such a representational regime. Nor, since such demonstrations of power were usually directed more to the court than to the general populace, was there any question of a democratic right of access to them. This principle, symbolized by the seizure of the Louvre, although it only achieved more generalizable and significantly modified forms in the mid-nineteenth century, generated a further contradiction between the conception of museums as instruments for the education of a democratic citizenry and the consequences of their functioning as instruments for the reform of public manners.

      While the former requires that they should address an undifferentiated public made up of free and formal equals, the latter, in giving rise to the development of various technologies for regulating or screening out the forms of behaviour associated with popular assemblies, has meant that they have functioned as a powerful means for differentiating populations. (Bennett 1995, 90–91)

      I thus argued, with regard to the principle of spectacle that informed the logic of royal palaces and other demonstrations of royal power through the public enactment of the scene of punishment or the public rituals of royalty, that spectacle did not, as Foucault suggested, disappear as punishment came to be secreted behind the closed walls of the penitentiary. Rather, as collections moved from the closed and private domains of royal and aristocratic households, or of literary, scientific, and philosophical associations, to become increasingly open and public, and as, particularly after 1851, the genre of the international exhibition developed into the most significant form of public entertainment/instruction of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, so the principle of spectacle migrated to this developing exhibitionary complex. In doing so it was articulated to two new principles of power: to the power of the commodity and of technology as the most potent public symbols of industrial capitalism; and to the power of the people-nation as the heir to the principle of sovereignty. If the first of these was most manifest in international exhibitions, the second was most evident in the development of national museums which, in the public symbolisms of their architectures just as much as in the thematic organization of their exhibits, embodied a new democratic conception of the principle of sovereignty in making the power of the people-nation publicly manifest to itself. This was not, however, the power of an alien, external force – not the power of an absolutism resting on dynastic or imperial principles4 – but a power arising out of, and related back to, the citizenries of the people-nations in whose name sovereign power was now exercised in ways that remained, and remain, equally marked by what Foucault characterized as the main principle of sovereign power, its circularity: that is, that it pursues itself and its own increase as an end in itself.

      There