Michael Walzer. J. Toby Reiner. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: J. Toby Reiner
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Афоризмы и цитаты
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781509526338
Скачать книгу
usual remit of political theory: he has written extensively on literature (see especially Walzer and Green, ed. 1969), urban planning (Walzer 1986e), technological development, and above all has produced much political commentary. This last was particularly important to both his early and his most recent work, including a striking call for Martin Luther King to run for the US Presidency in 1964 (Rosenblum and Walzer 1963). Not only does Walzer treat public-intellectual writing and political theory as more closely related than would most participants in both enterprises, but in important ways he prefers the former, arguing that a political theory that does not seek to enter into broader public discourse produces an “alienated politics” marked by “endless esotericism” (“State” 1989: 337–8). Such political theory is, Walzer holds, further from the world of political discourse than it should be and consequently tends toward intellectual elitism (Walzer 2007: 308), whereas public-intellectual magazines are “home to an ongoing conversation … a political argument in which many people participate” (Walzer 1994b: 165). Walzer became a political theorist because he wanted to make normative arguments about issues of pressing public concern (Walzer 2007: 306–9). His notion that political theorists have a license to make normative arguments is in effect the claim that they can act as public intellectuals. This makes Walzer a significant figure bearing in mind, as I discuss in the conclusion, a common story about American life that suggests that public intellectuals have been crowded out by academic specialization in recent decades (on this, see Furedi 2004, Jacoby 2000, Etzioni and Bowditch 2006; for discussion, Hauck 2010).

      In important ways, Walzer’s arguments for a more politically engaged approach anticipate the new “realism,” which is one of the major growth areas in Anglo-American political theory. Like Walzer, new realists argue that political theory must leave room for democratic decision-making and not seek to resolve political debates (Williams 2005: 3, Galston 2010: 390–4, Larmore 2013: 294–8). Insofar as realism is an offshoot of analytic political theory, Walzer’s criticisms should be understood as an internal critique of certain tendencies within the analytic approach, and especially of Rawlsian liberalism. However, Walzer’s particularism takes his critique a step beyond most realist arguments (for a fuller discussion on this point, see Reiner 2016: 383–5), which generally do not focus on variation in normative standards across cultures.

      Critics have often suggested that Walzer’s appeal to social meanings fails to recognize the degree of contestation, conflict, and domination that goes into processes of social construction.4 This points to a seeming paradox in Walzer’s career, when considered politically: while he has always defined himself as a social democrat and criticized liberalism from a position that he takes to be to its left, both liberals and radicals have often read his work as resting on somewhat conservative assumptions (see most notably Said 1986). Understanding Walzer, then, means coming to terms with the distance between his self-description as a leftist and an egalitarian and much of his reception. For example, in reviewing Spheres of Justice, Ronald Dworkin famously claimed that justice must be “our critic, not our mirror,” and that appeal to social meanings cannot be the basis for egalitarian political theory (Dworkin 1983a: 4, Cohen 1986, Daniels 1985). To liberals, Walzer’s approach seems to stifle individual freedom to choose a set of values to guide one’s life.