As Walzer bases his just-war theory on the claim that war has a moral reality and his theory of jus ad bellum on the war convention that he takes to be the product of that reality, Wars is replete with historical examples. It was important to Walzer that the examples be historical, both because his interest in justice in war emerged out of World War II and Vietnam and because he disliked the appeal to hypothetical examples deployed by members of the Society for Ethical and Legal Philosophy (Walzer 2015a: xxviii, 2007: 308; see discussion in Introduction). For Walzer, just-war theory must be both historical and political. For many recent just-war theorists, the techniques of analytic philosophy are a better foundation, because they lead to sharper analysis, while hypothetical examples allow us to abstract away from the confusion of the real world. Just as early critics of Wars suggested that Walzer’s theory of jus ad bellum went wrong because of its basis in the war convention, so more recent critics of his theory of jus in bello have made similar claims about his insistence that combatants have equal war rights. It is to this subject that we turn in Chapter 2.
Notes
1 Interview with author, April 19, 2010. 2 In particular, he has become more willing to countenance military humanitarian intervention than he was in 1977 (Walzer 2018: 53–76). 3 Orend argues that Walzer ought to have a theory of the justice of post-war settlements and reconstruction (jus post bellum) and reconstructs one along the lines he thinks Walzer ought to have taken (Orend 2000: 135–52, Orend 2013: 185–248; see also Patterson 2012a, 2012b). I postpone consideration of this issue until Chapter 6 so as to link it to Walzer’s skepticism about the cosmopolitan approach that underlies the project of developing principles of jus post bellum. 4 Most importantly, 2004b, but see also Walzer 1980a, 1988b, 1988c, 1992a, 2002b, 2006a, 2006b, and the forewords to all the subsequent editions of Wars. 5 The sixth proposition suggests an implicit theory of jus post bellum, which Orend calls the “retributive model” and criticizes (Orend 2013: 201–6), advocating instead “rehabilitation” designed to make aggressor states into law-abiding, rights-respecting members of international society (215–40). 6 According to Walzer, it was the Six-Day War that converted Dissentniks such as Irving Howe to Zionism. Interview with author, November 21, 2017.
Конец ознакомительного фрагмента.
Текст предоставлен ООО «ЛитРес».
Прочитайте эту книгу целиком, купив полную легальную версию на ЛитРес.
Безопасно оплатить книгу можно банковской картой Visa, MasterCard, Maestro, со счета мобильного телефона, с платежного терминала, в салоне МТС или Связной, через PayPal, WebMoney, Яндекс.Деньги, QIWI Кошелек, бонусными картами или другим удобным Вам способом.