Educational Explanations. Christopher Winch. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Christopher Winch
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Философия
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119816485
Скачать книгу
target="_blank" rel="nofollow" href="#ulink_45fa7aa4-0b8a-584f-ad40-7641cefa18aa">18 Although, as Lewis Carroll demonstrated through the story of Achilles and the Tortoise, such proofs depend on shared presuppositions (Carroll 1895).

      19 19 While Levi is right to deny that Ad Baculum is a genuine form of argument, since its content is nothing more than a threat, it may nevertheless be rational to respond to threats by acquiescence.

      20 20 Following Wilson (1959) a principle of charity is often recommended to researchers, in which subjects of research are assumed to be (constitutively) rational unless there is compelling evidence to the contrary. Although this is a useful principle, it can be misused if, for example, it is interpreted so as to take our ability to tolerate inconsistencies as a counter-instance. See Evans-Pritchard’s (1936) discussion of the inheritance of witchcraft substance for example (also discussed in Winch, P. 1964).

      21 21 Although that authority will usually be contextually circumscribed (Salmon 1984).

      22 22 For more discussion see Newton-Smith (1981), Rosenberg (2012).

      23 23 Perhaps echoing Hume’s identification of the primary sources of political allegiance in long habituation and legitimate succession (Hume 1739–40) Treatise of Human Nature, Bk III).

      24 24 We need to remind ourselves of what this can involve. Conducting a randomised control trial (RCT) is to investigate phenomena in a very particular way, abstracting from many of the features of phenomena as we ordinarily perceive them. Other forms of interventions study such as field and natural experiments are different again. Interviewing subjects to gain their perspective on phenomena is another way of doing so, while observing processes over an extended period of time is yet another. We should be wary of homogenising the different ways in which we engage with the world in carring out research by lumping them all together as ‘looking at reality’.

      25 25 A truth in the sense that it is never in experience contradicted. See Locke Essay on Human Understanding.

      26 26 But this does not mean that we lack resources for discussing such issues. A useful starting point might be the distinction between formal, non-formal and informal learning, for example.

      WHY IT IS NECESSARY TO DEFEND THE POSSIBILITY OF EER

      This chapter defends the claim that empirical educational research (EER) has a role in understanding educational practices and in solving educational problems. There is widespread scepticism about the value of EER, both in the philosophical community, but also among policymakers. There are (often justified) reservations about the quality of some research, but also a more radical scepticism about whether or not EER could be of any use. The former question will be returned to repeatedly during the course of this book, but this chapter will concentrate instead on the radical argument and show that it is incoherent.

      PHILOSOPHICAL SCEPTICISM ABOUT EMPIRICAL EDUCATIONAL RESEARCH

      This comes in five forms:

      1 Scepticism about whether or not there is an educational reality.

      2 Scepticism about whether we can know anything of general application about educational practices.

      3 A more pragmatic scepticism about whether or not it is possible to learn anything useful from EER.

      4 The idea that commonsense can tell us all we need to know about educational practices.

      5 The idea that one cannot research a good through empirical means.

      In practice, these positions are rarely, if ever, distinguished from each other. This means that the critique of scepticism has to make the distinctions in order to see which, if any, of the versions can be taken seriously.

      Scepticism about 1 is rarely stated openly. However, it does have distinctive philosophical roots which can be found in the phenomenological approach. Phenomenology argues that although we can distinguish subjective impressions from the perception of a non-subjective order, it does not follow that there is the same order for everyone. There are in fact multiple non-objective orders, depending on the perspective of those engaged with educational practices. We have already looked at this doctrine in the previous two chapters and have found it to be incoherent. It is based on an unduly rigorous conception of what it is for a proposition to be true. When truth does not measure up to that rigorous conception, the idea of an objective truth is abandoned in favour of a truth that is related to a particular perspective.

      Since we cannot determine whether or not a proposition corresponds with reality, the problem is solved by postulating a reality with which propositions can conform. That is reality seen from a particular perspective. Of course the perspective has to satisfy certain conditions before it can be taken seriously. There must be within that reality an objective succession (one that takes place irrespective of the point of viewer of the spectator) which can be coherently described which is ultimately based on the perceptions of the observer or the researcher. There must be some describable regularity about the phenomena observed; it must be possible to make meaningful predictions about what might happen and intervention and observance of the results of intervention must be possible. But we cannot infer from this that the educational reality thus described is the same for other observers or researchers using different approaches. Thus the satisfaction of these conditions does not entail that the reality thus described is the same for everyone.

      1 EER relies on inadequate conceptualisation of key explanatory factors (variables). See Barrow (1984) on school effectiveness and Davis (2012) on the teaching of reading.

      2 EER employs inappropriate methods of investigation and often poor designs (Barrow 1976).

      3 EER’s approach to explanation is flawed.

      4 EER fails to take account of contextual variation and (a variant on this) assumes stable forms of identity which do not in fact exist (Davis 2015, on the school).

      5 Most EER findings turn out to be false (Carr, D. 2003).