The Perspective of Love. R. J. Snell. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: R. J. Snell
Издательство: Ingram
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Религия: прочее
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781630873431
Скачать книгу
Theatetus describes a recent conversation with his teacher, Theodorus, on the nature of mathematical squares. Beginning with instances, Theodorus proceeded sequentially to work through the numbers, “the power of 3 square feet and the power of 5 square feet . . . and he went on in this way, taking each case in turn till he came to the power of 17 square feet; there for some reason he stopped. So the idea occurred to us that, since the powers were turning out to be unlimited in number, we might try to collect the powers in question under one term, which would apply to them all.”95 Lonergan provides a similar example in the following series, “1+1=2; 2+1=3; 3+1=4; etc., etc., etc. . . .” suggesting that the most important aspect in the example is “etc., etc., etc. . . .” for “. . .” indicates that the process can go on indefinitely under a rule or formula.96 Like Theatetus, one can stop, realize that the instances are potentially unlimited in number, and provide an explanatory formula rather than working through each and every instance. In so doing, one has grasped necessity in the relations, what must be present for the relations to be intelligible rather than accidental, and the “single term” or formula articulates what is necessarily present in the intelligibility of each instance covered by the formula, precisely the anticipation of the Socratic method’s search for a definition including each relevant instance while excluding each instance of a different kind.

      Theory and the Real

      Although articulated differently, both Plato and Aristotle consider the formal necessity grasped in theory to be real and objectively knowable, and thus metaphysics became the master science. In common sense, the real was envisioned as bodies, as the “already out there now real,” or presence, what could be seen or touched, because common sense begins with an anticipation of what exists in relation to me and my sensation. Since concern is for that which exists in relation to me, I expect that what exists is that which exists over and against me, and being is modeled after bodies. With theory, being is whatever is intended as meaningful, and only the invariant and necessary is fully meaningful:

      Metaphysics is a science, and thus will follow the rules of the other sciences, just having greater extension and thus abstraction, but metaphysics follows entirely the rules implicit in theory’s anticipation of meaning.

      Theory as Law

      Note the anticipation for data to “conform to some law.” The heuristic shapes what we anticipate, and thus how we interpret what we find, in an interesting pivoting of discovery and anticipation. We anticipate intelligibility under a certain heuristic, thereby discovering such intelligibility in the data given to us. For instance, Theatetus mentions that Theodorus began to teach about squares with the assistance of diagrams, namely, that which could be viewed and imagined, so to arrive at the formula after the intelligible principle was discovered through the use of the data supplied by the diagrams. But many people could look at the diagrams and find no intelligibility; only those anticipating finding something, only those looking for something, some unknown x of a certain type find x. Once found, the formula governs the anticipation of how additional instances will be understood, even before those instances are diagramed. So our anticipation allows for discovery which provides the basis for ongoing anticipation.

      Theoretical Natural Law—The Default

      Jacques Maritain summarizes much of the classical tradition of natural law when he writes: