Since the various common sense natural laws continue, so too the tensions and questions regarding their meaning and adequacy. It’s not as though Antigone settled once and for all the difference between what it means to be a good citizen and what it means to be a good human, and Socrates certainly put no end to the sophists among us, or to the force of custom and habit. Consequently, while we can trace how the tensions and questions within the historical past prompted developments within natural law as it moved from common sense to the theoretical mode of meaning, those very tensions and questions can be discerned in contemporary scholarship and debate. Understanding the role of differentiation in how meaning is made requires a move from common sense to theory to explain how there are yet more “natures” to identify and grasp, yet more accounts of natural law to investigate. We turn, thus, to the second mode of meaning, the theoretical.
41. Budziszewski, The Line Through the Heart, 199.
42. Ibid.
43. Ibid., 200.
44. Strauss, Natural Right and History, 7–8.
45. MacIntyre, “Theories of Natural Law in the Culture of Advanced Modernity,” 94.
46. For the rationality of Thomism as a tradition, see MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry, 127–49.
47. Lonergan, Understanding and Being, 4–20; Snell and Cone, Authentic Cosmopolitanism, 1–12, 44–65.
48. Ibid., 4–5.
49. Lonergan, Insight, 29.
50. Lonergan, Understanding and Being, 5.
51. Lonergan, Insight, 34.
52. Lonergan, Understanding and Being, 13.
53. Ibid., 14.
54. Lonergan, Insight, 197.
55. Ibid.
56. Ibid., 198.
57. Lonergan, Understanding and Being, 87.
58. Lonergan, Insight, 202.
59. Ibid., 90.
60. Ibid., 203.
61. Ibid., 205. This is the underlying premise of Snell and Cone, Authentic Cosmopolitanism and its articulation of the education of love—the world is, for us, as we love it; if our loves are properly ordered, so too the world.
62. For an exposition on these patterns of organization, see Lonergan, Insight, 204–12; Snell, Through a Glass Darkly, 86–91.
63. Plato, Republic, 338a–344d in Collected Dialogues of Plato.
64. Plato, Gorgias, 482e in Collected Dialogues of Plato.
65. Ibid., 483d–484b.
66. Voegelin, Plato, 32.
67. Plato, Gorgias, 508a in Collected Dialogues of Plato.
68. Plato, Republic, 331a–b in Collected Dialogues of Plato.
69. Voegelin, Plato, 57.
70. Aeschylus, Aeschylus I.
71. Lonergan, Insight, 275–82.
72. Ibid., 276.
73. Snell and Cone, Authentic Cosmopolitanism, 23–31.
74. This need not be unintelligent. Descartes’s whole project, one shaping the modern problematic for both empiricists and idealists was modeled on the image of the mind “in here,” the world “out there,” and ideas as a veil “in between.” The best thinkers followed suit, all of them trying to solve the theoretical problems of epistemology and metaphysics with an image borrowed from an utterly distinct mode of meaning. See Snell, Through a Glass Darkly, 9–40.
75. Voegelin, Anamnesis, 59.
76. Westphal, God, Guilt, and Death, 195.
77. Jaeger, Paideia, 155.
78. Ibid., 165. For the notion of philosophy