Thinking the Event. François Raffoul. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: François Raffoul
Издательство: Ingram
Серия: Studies in Continental Thought
Жанр произведения: Философия
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9780253045386
Скачать книгу
as if the possible was “possibilized” by the impossible. Indeed, a possibility that would be merely possible can only be a neutralization of the irruptive nature of the event. “For a possible that would only be possible (non-impossible), a possible surely and certainly possible, accessible in advance, would be a poor possible, a futureless possible, a possible already set aside, so to speak, life-assured” (PF, 29). Such a possible would not be eventful, but the predetermined realization of a prior plan or program. If the event must be approached first on the side of the possible, it must be recognized that the impossible proves to be the secret resource of the possible. “If all that arises is what is already possible, and so capable of being anticipated and expected, that is not an event. The event is possible only coming from the impossible” (PM, 74).

      I pursue this thinking of the event of being in terms of a reflection on presence. As noted, Heidegger approaches being as an event, as the event of presence. Instead of supposing an underlying permanent substance and foundation, it is a matter of understanding being as the event of givenness (and withdrawal), as well as a letting. Indeed, “letting” is for Heidegger the “deepest meaning of being.” For an event happens of itself so that an event is never prepared, produced, or made, but precisely let be. To the letting of being corresponds the fundamental disposition of thinking as Gelassenheit, as letting-be. “Thinking the event” would mean here: letting . . . the letting, letting the letting be. Through a close reading of the 1962 lecture “On Time and Being” and other texts of that late period, such as Four Seminars, I engage Heidegger’s approach to being as event of presence (Anwesenheit) or presencing (Anwesen). What then appears is how the proper of time and the proper of being involve the event (Ereignis) of the givenness of the es gibt, that is to say, the event of being and time and the human being as recipient of such event. This is why in a last section, I show how the self happens in and though the event of being, a self that is no longer the substantial subject of the tradition, but the one who is the recipient of the event of being, happening through the happening of being. The thinking of being approached from the giving of Ereignis leads to a pure thinking of the event, that is, to the eventfulness of the event, an eventfulness that nonetheless always entails an irreducible expropriation.

      In chapter 7, I explore such expropriation in the happening of the event in terms of what Jean-Luc Nancy calls a withdrawal of essence. This withdrawal is apparent in the fact that nothing preexists the event of being, no principle, arche, or prior substance. “Being absolutely does not preexist; nothing preexists; only what exists exists” (BSP, 29). To that extent, being is nothing but the event of itself and does not refer to any other instance than its own happening. The event is no longer anchored in a principle that itself would not be happening. Preceded by nothing and grounded in no essence, the event can only come as a surprise. Indeed, for Nancy, the surprise is not the mere accompanying aspect of an event, but its defining characteristic (“What makes the event an event is not only that it happens, but that it surprises,” BSP, 159), going so far as to write that “the event surprises or else it is not an event” (BSP, 167). The event cannot unfold predictably, following an essence, a direction, or some principle, but can only happen “by way of surprise” (BSP, 159). Thinking the event here would mean thinking the surprise, which immediately reverses into: thinking is surprised by the event; surprised, or, to follow literally the French, sur-prise: “over-taken.” Nancy writes that “philosophy is surprised thought” (BSP, 165).

      I unfold this essencelessness of the event in terms of what Nancy calls the “creation of the world.” In spite of its theological provenance, the motif of “creation,” certainly used provocatively by Nancy,37 is to be taken in a radically nontheological way as a creation “without a creator.”38 In fact, creation is even characterized as the nodal point in a deconstruction of Christianity to the extent that it is a creation ex nihilo, a nothing in which God as author disappears. Nancy suggests that the God of ontotheology, in a peculiar kenosis or self-emptying, was “progressively stripped of the divine attributes of an independent existence and only retained those of the existence of the world considered in its immanence” (CW, 44). Creation, understood is a nontheological sense, is the mark of the event of the world: the world is not given, not resting on some prior principle of arche, but exists rigorously as the event of itself, as creation of itself. This is why Nancy clarifies that “the world is not given” and that, in fact, “the world is its own creation” (CW, 109).

      In a third section, I explore this thinking of the event in terms of abandonment, which designates the unsubstantial character of an event as deprived of principles, ground and arche, a condition or rather “incondition” in which we find ourselves in the wake of the exhaustion of metaphysical principles and from which we are called to think. Nancy characterizes existence as abandonment and sheer exposure, a “leaving” or “abandonment” of any prior essence. It is “from an abandonment that being comes forth: we can say no more. There is no going back prior; being conveys nothing older than its abandonment.”39 The only ontology that remains, according to Nancy, is precisely no longer an ontotheology, but an ontology characterized by the feature of abandonment, that is, abandonment as the sole predicate of being. Abandonment must not only be understood as an abandonment by but also an abandonment to a law, Nancy clarifies. One finds here the motif of law and obligation intertwined with that of “abandoned being.” The event of being amounts to a being-obligated: to be is having to be, obligated and called to be. One can speak of a categorical imperative of the event of being: one must be! A certain dignity, or ethicality, is hence conferred to the event of being, which is always a call that one must answer.

      Finally, I explore the extent to which this event of being is always—each time—the event of a coexistence, as for Nancy being rigorously means: being-with. Nancy approaches such being-with as an event in his rethinking of democracy, of what one may call the event of democracy. Nancy’s claim is that it is a matter of understanding democracy “metaphysically,” and not in its traditional exhausted sense as a political regime. “Democracy is first of all a metaphysics and only afterwards a politics.”40 What Nancy gestures toward here is to approach democracy not as a political form or regime, but as an event. Indeed, democracy is characterized as a power of imagining, of invention, without subject or mastery and in excess of identity of any given form. Democracy is not only in excess of the political, it is also in excess of itself, that is, of its own idea, form, or concept, precisely to the extent that it is first of all an event, which, as seen with Arendt, always exceeds its own concept. Therein lies what Nancy calls the “inadequacy” of democracy, an inadequacy with respect to itself that Nancy refers to Derrida’s “democracy to come” in a perspective that combines the eventful character of democracy with its incompleteness and perfectibility. I argue that such incompletion or inadequation—indeed différance—must be also thought from the eventful character of democracy.

      In chapter 8, I focus on the inappropriability of the event, a motif that has been a constant thread in the course of this work. As I have hoped to show, the event permeates every instance of being and existence to such an extent that to be means: to happen. And yet, it remains inappropriable, frustrating any attempt to reduce it to a present being or an identity. It only happens, in the flash of a disjointed, discontinuous, and anachronic temporality preventing any gathering in a present. The event has, as it were, the structure of the trace as Derrida describes it: “The trace is not a substance, a present existing thing, but a process that is changing all the time. It can only reinterpret itself and always, finally, it is carried away” (PM, 159). The event remains inappropriable, resistant to anticipation and even to comprehension, irreducible to reason. It “belongs to an atemporal temporality, to a duration that cannot be grasped: something one can neither stabilize, establish, grasp [prendre], apprehend, or comprehend. Understanding, common sense, and reason cannot seize [begreifen], conceive, understand, or mediate it.”41 As such, the event constitutes a challenge to reason and understanding: “The event is what comes and, in coming, comes to surprise me, to surprise and to suspend comprehension: the event is first of all that which I do not first of all comprehend. Better, the