A Companion to the Political Culture of the Roman Republic. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: История
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119673590
Скачать книгу
republic. In this way, Machiavelli offers his work as a correction of Livy and as a vision of the hitherto unimagined opportunities and possibilities latent in republican politics. By radicalising certain aspects of Livy’s presentation of Roman virtue, Machiavelli reorients its relationship to nature, fortune and tradition. In doing so, he all but stands Livy’s virtue on its head. Rather than being reverent, devoted, traditional, obedient, self-sacrificing and nobly committed to the common good, true virtue, for Machiavelli, is youthful, dangerous, innovative, treacherous, self-interested and above all hostile to Fortune (Liv. 1.18, 1.26, 2.13, 3.26, 4.14, 5.27, 7.10, 8.36, 9.4, 10.24; Rossi 2004: 377 n. 42). Moreover, instead of being prized for its intrinsic worth or nobility, Machiavellian virtù is purely instrumental, desirable because it is the only reliable way to acquire security, prosperity and glory in this world. Virtù both lowers human excellence by making it instrumental and raises its profile by pitting it as a successful rival to fortune (P 15, 25; D 2.30.5, 3.9.1, 3.36.1–2, 3.43.1).

      Are we all Machiavellians now? It would be hard to find a Roman historian nowadays who explains the city’s success with reference to traditional virtue rather than material power and efficient political causation. Even so, Machiavelli occupies a position at the crossroads of current discussions of political virtue, freedom and power. On the one hand, he has frequently been interpreted as an admirer of ancient Roman freedom and virtue, and hence as the author of modern ‘republicanism’, a term of theory that pinpoints specific ideals such as political independence, freedom from arbitrary control and an active civic life (Honohan 2002: Chapter 2; Pettit 1997: 4–7, 19, 28–31; 2012: ‘Introduction’; Skinner 1978; 1990; Viroli 1998; Pocock 2003). Did Machiavelli take a promising theory of engaged citizenship derived from ancient Rome, Aristotle and Cicero and channel it into the modern world, where it might prove attractive even to citizens of the contemporary liberal-democratic nation state (see Chapter 22)? On the other hand, ever since his writings first became public, Machiavelli has been construed as a malign force, a manipulative deceiver, a guide to all that is unholy, untrustworthy and selfish – hardly the attributes that respectable republican theorists would want to cultivate among their citizens. Is Machiavellian modernity, then, hostile to ancient virtue precisely because of the Florentine’s concentration on utilitarian success and unconstrained projections of power (Strauss [1958] 1978; Hulliung 1983; Sullivan 1996; Mansfield 1979)? It is impossible to establish Machiavelli’s influence on the interpretation of the Roman Republic without also keeping these charged theoretical dilemmas in mind.

      2.2 Virtue and Origins

      Reading backwards in time, however, Machiavelli’s