Western Philosophy. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Афоризмы и цитаты
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119165743
Скачать книгу
the basic attitude because it is entirely free from any reference to objects. The harmonious feeling or attitude, which the metaphysician tries to express in a moralistic system, is more clearly expressed in the music of Mozart. And when a metaphysician gives verbal expression to his dualistic-heroic attitude towards life in a dualistic system, is it not perhaps because he lacks the ability of a Beethoven to express this attitude in an adequate medium? Metaphysicians are musicians without musical ability. Instead they have a strong inclination to work within the medium of the theoretical, to connect concepts and thoughts. Now, instead of activating, on the one hand, this inclination in the domain of science, and satisfying, on the other hand, the need for expression in art, the metaphysician confuses the two and produces a structure which achieves nothing for knowledge and something inadequate for the expression of attitude.

      Specimen Questions

      1 Why did Carnap maintain that much traditional metaphysics was not just false but meaningless? Is his view defensible?

      2 What are the conditions for meaningful statements, and why are metaphysically meaningful statements impossible, according to Carnap?

      3 Explain why Carnap thinks metaphysicians are ‘musicians without musical ability’.

      Suggestions for Further Reading (Including Internet Resources)

      1 R. Carnap, ‘The Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language’ [Überwindung der Metaphysik durch Logische Analyse der Sprache, 1932]. English version in the following useful collection with a valuable introduction by the editor: A. J. Ayer (ed.), Logical Positivism (New York: Free Press, 1959).

      2 See also O. Hanfling (ed.), Essential Readings in Logical Positivism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1987); A. J. Ayer (ed.), Language, Truth and Logic (2nd edn, London: Gollancz, 1946); P. Schlipp, The Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1963).

      3 In terms of online resources, you can find a good overview of logical empiricism which lists Carnap as one of the central contributors to the movement in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy at https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logical-empiricism/ (by R. Creath). The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy has an entry on Carnap at https://www.iep.utm.edu/carnap/ (by M. Murzi); for this topic see section 4 on meaning and verifiability and for an entry on Carnap’s modal logic see https://www.iep.utm.edu/cmlogic/ (by M. Cresswell).

      4 For ample information on Carnap and useful links to his works go to http://www.carnap.org/maintained by D. Marshall (University of Minnesota).

      5 The BBC program In Our Time has a podcast in which M. Bragg and guests discuss Logical Positivism, the radical philosophy of the Vienna Circle. You can listen to it by going to https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/b00lbsj3 (2009).

      Notes

      * Rudolf Carnap, ‘The Elimination of Metaphysics through Logical Analysis of Language’ [Überwindung der Metaphysik durch Logische Analyse der Sprache, 1932]. First published in Erkenntnis, vol. II. Trans. Arthur Pap, in A. J. Ayer (ed.), Logical Positivism (New York: Free Press, 1959), pp. 60–80; abridged.

      Our final extract, by the American thinker Willard Van Orman Quine, one of the most distinguished analytic philosophers of the twentieth century, takes a robustly down-to-earth approach to philosophical questions about ontology or being. Quine begins by addressing the ‘Platonic riddle’ of non-being: how can we talk coherently about non-existent entities (like Father Christmas, or the mythical winged horse, Pegasus)? Talking about these beings is surely not the same as talking about nothing, so must we not concede that they have some sort of being?

      In responding to this puzzle, Quine avows a ‘taste for desert landscapes’. To avoid cluttering up our ontology with all sorts of dubious entities, like non-existent beings, and merely possible (as opposed to actual) beings, like the ‘possible fat man in the doorway’, Quine follows the lead of Bertrand Russell (see Part III, extract 9, below) and proposes to analyse statements referring to such putative entities by using ‘quantificational words’ or ‘bound variables’ – expressions such as ‘there is something such that …’. So the statement ‘the round square cupola on Berkeley College is wooden’, instead of being taken to refer to some weird non-existent entity, would simply come out as the false assertion ‘there is something such that it is round and it is square and it is atop Berkeley College and it is wooden’.

      One great advantage of this approach is that it avoids our being misled by what look like names into supposing that some entity must be being referred to: ‘names are … altogether immaterial to the ontological issue, for [they] can be converted into descriptions’; and by the use of bound variables, ‘descriptions can be eliminated’. Quine’s manoeuvre here exemplifies a characteristic feature of the analytic school of philosophy in the mid to late twentieth century – the tendency to ‘defuse’ portentous metaphysical issues by the use of careful logical and linguistic analysis.

      Another significant and influential aspect of Quine’s approach, which emerges towards the end of our extract, is the respect it accords to science as a model for philosophy. Our acceptance of an ontology, Quine argues, is similar to our acceptance of a scientific theory, such as a system of physics: ‘we adopt … the simplest conceptual scheme into which the disordered fragments of raw experiences can be fitted and arranged.’ There are no absolute rules here: what will be the most convenient ontology will depend on our ‘various interests and purposes’. But with simplicity as the watchword, and making sense of ‘raw experiences’ as the basic test, many of the grand metaphysical schemes of earlier philosophers are destined, in the Quinean scheme of things, to lose much of their appeal.

      Though Quine’s largely deflationary conception of metaphysics has exerted considerable influence on subsequent philosophizing, the more ambitious traditional idea of the metaphysician as mapping out the ultimate categories of reality has by no means disappeared, and the future of course of metaphysics is hard to predict. What seems clear, in the light of our survey of some of the principal approaches to ‘being and reality’ in the Western tradition, is that future philosophers are unlikely to resist the perennial appeal of raising fundamental general questions about the ultimate nature of the world and our place within it.

      A curious thing about the ontological problem is its simplicity. It can be put in three Anglo-Saxon monosyllables: ‘What is there?’ It can be answered, moreover, in a word – ‘Everything’ – and everyone will accept this answer as true. However, this is merely to say that there is what there is. There remains room for disagreement over cases; and so the issue has stayed alive down the centuries.

      When I try to formulate our difference of opinion, on the other hand, I seem to be in a predicament. I cannot admit that there are some things which McX countenances and I do not, for in admitting that there are such things I should be contradicting my own rejection of them.