Western Philosophy. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Афоризмы и цитаты
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119165743
Скачать книгу
(or belief) is located between pure being and absolute not-being so that it amounts to neither knowledge nor complete ignorance. How does Socrates argue for this claim and what does it tell us about the objects of opinion?

      1 Plato, Republic. Many translations are available, including F. M. Cornford (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1941) and H. P. D. Lee (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1955).

      2 General introductions to Plato’s thought include J. C. Gosling, Plato> (London: Routledge, 1973), and A. E. Taylor, Plato: The Man and His Work (5th edn, London: Methuen, 1948).

      3 For a useful guide to Plato’s Republic and in particular this topic, see G. Santas, Understanding Plato’s Republic, Ch. 7 (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010).

      4 There is an excellent account of Plato’s views on knowledge in J. Annas, An Introduction to Plato’s Republic (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980).

      5 The nature of knowledge is discussed in many other works of Plato, especially the Theaetetus. A good starting point is F. M. Cornford, Plato’s Theory of Knowledge (London: Routledge, 1960). See also I. M. Crombie, An Examination of Plato’s Doctrines, vol. II (London: Routledge, 1963); N. P. White, Plato on Knowledge and Reality (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1976); R. Kraut (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plato (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), esp. chs 6, 9.

      6 In the following podcast M. M. McCabe and P. Adamson discuss Plato’s notion of knowledge: https://historyofphilosophy.net/plato-knowledge. For further related short podcasts on Plato by P. Adamson go to https://historyofphilosophy.net/plato-life.

      7 For a couple of excellent online entries, see the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy at https://www.iep.utm.edu/republic/ (by A. Coumoundouros), and the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy at https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/ (by R. Kraut). See also the Stanford Encyclopedia entry ‘The Analysis of Knowledge’.

      Notes

      * Plato, Republic [Politeia, c.380 BC], Bk V, 474b–483e. Trans. B. Jowett, in The Dialogues of Plato (Oxford: Clarendon, 1892), vol. III, pp. 171–9.

      1 1 A man who was not a man (a eunuch) threw a stone that was not a stone (a pumice stone) at a bird that was not a bird (a bat) sitting on a twig that was not a twig (a reed).

      3 Demonstrative Knowledge and Its Starting Points: Aristotle, Posterior Analytics*

      Readers of the preceding extracts may feel inclined to agree with Plato that knowledge is superior to mere opinion, and that it needs to go beyond the particular to some more abstract level of rational justification; but they may also feel sceptical both about the notion of innate sources of knowledge (put forward in the Meno) and also about the sharp contrast (in the Republic) between the visible and the intelligible realms, which seems to downgrade the role of ordinary sensory information as a source of knowledge. The following extract from Aristotle puts pressure on both these Platonic ideas.

      Plato, as we have seen (extract 1), believed that the mind has innate knowledge of certain self-evident truths. But Aristotle questions the suggestion that the starting points for knowledge have to be innate, stressing instead the crucial role of sense-perception in providing the raw materials of knowledge. Knowledge must involve going beyond particular instances, and grasping universal truths, but this need not, according to Aristotle, imply the existence of abstract Forms over and above particular objects and groups of objects. Rather, knowledge develops naturally from sense-perception, since the human mind has the capacity for noticing and remembering general similarities which underlie the flux of sensory experience. This faculty for grasping the universal in the particular is called by Aristotle nous or ‘intuition’ (though he does not succeed in making it clear just how the results of intuition are supposed to have the self-evidence and certainty needed to serve as the starting points for scientific demonstration).

      All teaching and all intellectual learning arises from pre-existing knowledge. This is evident if we look at all the examples. For the mathematical sciences are acquired in this way, as is each of the other arts. The same goes for arguments – both syllogistic and inductive, for both produce instruction by means of what we are already aware of …

      We consider we have scientific knowledge or understanding of something … when- ever we consider we know that the cause of the item in question is its cause, and that it is not possible for it to be otherwise. So it is clear that having scientific knowledge is something of this sort. For both those who do and those who do not have knowledge think that they are in this situation, the latter merely believing it, while the former are actually in it. Hence scientific knowledge relates to that which cannot be otherwise.

      We shall discuss later whether there is also another way of knowing. But we can state now that there is knowledge through demonstration. By demonstration I mean a scientific syllogism, and by this I mean one whose possession constitutes scientific knowledge.

      If knowledge is indeed what we have just proposed, demonstrative knowledge must necessarily depend on premises which are true, primary, immediate, and better known than, and prior to and causes of, the conclusion … Without such conditions there can be syllogisms, but not be a demonstration, since it will not produce scientific knowledge …

      Since it is impossible for that of which there is knowledge to be otherwise, that which is known through demonstrative knowledge must be necessary. Demonstrative knowledge is the knowledge we have in virtue of having a demonstration. A demonstration therefore is a syllogistic deduction from necessary premises …