Museum Theory. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Изобразительное искусство, фотография
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119796558
Скачать книгу
sometimes especially) if nothing is known about their provenance or use (as I have written elsewhere: Dudley 2012). This is not only because of the overall visual impact of the object or its content but also, as my brief exploration of different elements of the torn Bacon paintings illustrates, as a result of the optical examination of details in the artifact. Furthermore, even when sight is the only sense we can directly utilize, we nonetheless activate our memory and imagination in order to bring other sensory modalities into the perception we create. That is, when our eyes rove over the details of something, we build in our minds an idea not only of what it looks like but also, for example, of its three-dimensional form and texture, thus developing an imagined sense of what the object feels like too. Recent scientific research is helpful here, not only evidencing the claim that engaging with art and other objects can have significant effects on affect and well-being (Chatterjee, Vreeland, and Nobel 2009; Binnie 2013), but also demonstrating that viewers of authentic material objects will look at them for longer and in different ways to digital reproductions, their eyes exploring more of the whole artifact and looking more closely at physical details (Binnie 2013; see also Quian Quiroga, Dudley, and Binnie 2011).

      Yet the physical qualities of objects in museum contexts or elsewhere remain inadequately explored in the material culture literature as a factor in the relationships between people and things. There are of course many exceptions, just one example of which might be Keane’s semiotic investigation of the role of materiality in causation, in which he explores the “bundling” of qualities in a particular object and “the historicity inherent to signs in their very materiality” (2005, 183; emphasis original). Others have written extensively on the “agency” of objects. For some this can be a useful notion, when agency is understood as not necessarily implying intentionality (e.g., Gell 1998; Gosden 2005), but for others it remains problematic, with true agency attributable only to human subjects (e.g., Morphy 2009; Knell 2012). Conversely, the agentive actants of actor network theory may be human, animal, or object (e.g., Latour 1993; Law and Hassard 1999). Thus, it seems we have yet to find a satisfactory theoretical alternative that adequately or convincingly accounts for the reality that perception, cognition, and emotional and physical responses are actively affected by the real-world characteristics of objects (see Ingold 2010), notwithstanding that individuals may see, interpret, and react differently depending on the cultural experiences they bring with them.

      There are significant potential applications of these insights from postcolonial studies to the museum encounter. At O’Hanlon’s (1988, 199) theoretical level, the imbalance of power inherent in the encounter relationship is reinforced, but then immediately we are reminded of the need to avoid generalities and to heed the real complexities involved. Utilizing the colonial metaphor enables us to be aware of the severe difficulties in trying to “see” things from the object’s perspective and prompts us to look beyond our established sources, methods, theories, and concerns in order to seek out alternative ways of trying to understand the viewpoints of things in museums. We are also reminded that subject/object categories, connections, or distinctions can be profitable at the theoretical level but need to be avoided – in fixed and essentialist forms, at any rate – on the substantive plane, where we should focus instead on what actually happens in person–thing engagements. Furthermore, just as it is extraordinarily difficult to see things from the colonized’s perspective, so may it be almost impossible to comprehend the object’s point of view – and it will certainly remain impossible if we fail to look beyond our established sources, methods, theories, and concerns in order to seek out alternative modes of perception and cognition.

      So, continuing the metaphor, as the colonized gazed back at the colonizers and formed their own opinions of them just as much as the other way around, let us suppose that this is indeed also what museum objects do. Let us imagine that they too have points of view, and that they look on the visitor just as much as she peers at them. This is not in itself an original suggestion. In encountering “startling” pieces, Knappett says, we find not only ourselves looking at them, but them looking back (2007, 136). This is the reciprocal contemplatory regard in which, as Knappett describes in commenting on Garrow and Shove’s (2007) experiment with a rock and a toothbrush, the “strange” can become “ordinary,” or vice versa. Knappett, citing Oppenheim’s Objet, Duchamp’s Bottle Rack, and Dali’s Lobster Telephone, finds in this experiment an echo of “the