Contemporary Sociological Theory. Группа авторов. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Группа авторов
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Социология
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119527237
Скачать книгу
decline of the American urban political boss to the rise of divorce and family instability.

      Due to constitutional and legal arrangements, among other factors, the competition among providers of joint goods is often restricted. The less competitive the market for the joint good is, the greater the dependence of group members. This means that the obligations (taxes) that the members of different groups adopt for the production of the same joint good are likely to vary. As the cost of leaving a group rises, so does the net benefit of remaining in it. And the greater this benefit is, the greater the willingness to tolerate extensive obligations. Although the average dependence of group members may vary, it never disappears altogether, for the members of groups always depend upon the efforts of others for the production of joint goods. The solitary consumer of private goods, however, need not incur dependence.

      Since it permits the initial members of a group to demand higher obligations of new members, dependence also has implications for the evolution of group hierarchy. The older members’ ability to extract what in effect are rents from newer ones is, however, limited by the dependence of these new members. The less their dependence, the less extensive the obligations they will incur.

      In summary, then, the greater the dependence of members, the greater the extensiveness of group obligations. The extensiveness of a group’s obligations alone, however, has no necessary implications for group solidarity. What also matters is the probability that members will comply with these obligations. It is to this problem that I now turn.

      The Probability of Compliance

      The relationship between control and compliance is intricate for two reasons. In the first place, the group must have sufficient resources at its disposal to effectively reward or punish its members contingent on their level of contribution or performance. This ability to provide what are essentially selective incentives can be called the group’s sanctioning capacity.

      By virtue of the fact that members are more or less dependent (by definition), all groups have at least one potential sanction ‒ namely, exclusion from the group. Exclusion is the ultimate sanction in that it denies individuals access to the jointly produced good that they value. Yet some groups use this sanction more readily than others. For example, intentional communities are more likely to expel deviant members than are families. Though the effectiveness of the threat of expulsion varies with the member’s dependence on the group, the group’s willingness to employ it as a sanction is analytically distinct from the dependence of its members.

      In any case, many groups employ additional sanctions that fall short of expulsion to motivate compliance with corporate obligations. Although these sanctions are collectively produced, they are quite different from the benefits that lead people to join the group initially. Like exclusion, many of these sanctions are negative and therefore cannot count as benefits at all: if members do not live up to their obligations, they will suffer the consequences. In further contrast to the good that motivates membership, the provision of sanctions need not be regular or guaranteed but can be intermittent and provisional. A union’s strike pay, for example, can be an incentive for picketing, but it only comes into play during a strike.

      In order to be effective, these sanctions must be distributed to members selectively. Whether these sanctions are material or nonmaterial, their supply is never unlimited. Thus, to attain maximum compliance, groups must not only devise means of producing or procuring stores of adequate sanctions, but they must also convince all members that they will receive the particular sanction that is appropriate to their past behavior. If compliant members are consistently punished while noncompliant ones are consistently rewarded, then the overall level of compliance will be at its nadir. And if there is too long a delay between behavior and subsequent sanctioning, the efficacy of a sanction declines.

      The second reason for the intricacy of the relationship between control and compliance is that the group must be able to detect whether individuals comply with their obligations or not. This is its monitoring capacity. Monitoring is problematic because individual behavior is often difficult to observe, much less to measure. Some acts ‒ those conducted in utter privacy ‒ are intrinsically harder to monitor than others ‒ those carried out in the full view of other members. When a group tries to attain attitudinal as against visible behavioral compliance, its monitoring task is all the more demanding.

      True, not all members have an interest in concealing their behavior. Deviants alone have this incentive, but the compliant can usually be relied upon to publicize their virtue. Yet this does not mean that groups composed of the relatively virtuous can do without monitoring. Monitoring is required not only to ferret out the noncompliant but also to check on the allegedly compliant, for claims of virtuous behavior can never be taken at face value. In the absence of monitoring, deviants or shirkers are also likely to describe their past behavior as virtuous. Hence, all self–reports of compliance must be sifted to separate the wheat from the chaff, and this, in turn, requires monitoring.

      Altogether, then, noncompliance with obligations (and with rules of any sort) can have at least two separate roots: it can be due to inadequate sanctioning or to impaired monitoring. Since each of these activities is costly, the total costs of control constitute a severe constraint on any group’s ability to attain compliance.

      What determines a group’s control capacity? Many considerations come into play [… ], and for illustrative purposes I shall only mention two of them here.

      The first determinant is the measurability of the individual’s contribution. Whenever an individual’s contribution to the production of a joint good cannot be reliably indicated by an output ‒ as is the case, for example, in teamwork ‒ control is problematic. Since acts carried out in privacy are more difficult to monitor than public acts, another factor is the group’s ability to limit the privacy of its members. It is in the interest of members to extend their privacy, just as it is in the interest of the collective to limit it.

      A group’s survival depends upon the adoption of effective techniques to control its members. Yet insofar as control enables group members to produce joint goods, it must be considered a second–order collective good (Laver 1981: 62–71). As such, the provision of control is itself subject to the free–rider dilemma. While each member may gain from the overall solidarity of the group (because solidarity is an enabling condition for the supply of the joint good), free riding remains each rational agent’s best strategy. Members will not voluntarily assume the burden of control without sufficient compensation. It follows that all long–lived groups must include some individuals ‒ sometimes called agents ‒ who are compensated for providing control and are motivated to do it on this account. Without such agents groups cannot secure routine compliance. But agents come in varying sizes and shapes. In informal groups everyone is simultaneously an agent and a member; in more complex structures agents and members are differentiated and perform mutually exclusive roles. In some groups (American academic departments) members rotate into and out of the agency role; in others (capitalist firms) access to this role is more restricted. Different institutional arrangements ‒ particularly those that affect the distribution of the joint good ‒ determine the relations between agents and members in all groups.

      Whereas