This is Philosophy of Science. Franz-Peter Griesmaier. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Franz-Peter Griesmaier
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Математика
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119758006
Скачать книгу
familiar physical objects that surround us.1 This is the reason that the proposed analysis of the notion of evidence refers to both unobserved and unobservable features.

      This last observation leads to a further important fact concerning our ordinary concept of evidence. We think that our beliefs about the world have to be properly responsive to empirical evidence, and if they are not, those beliefs appear irrational. Thus, there is an important connection between being rational and being responsive to evidence. This connection will be the topic of later chapters. For now, our next task is to discuss what items in the “world” are appropriate candidates for evidence.

      2.2 Basic Evidence and Derived Evidence

      2.2.1 What We See

      One question that many philosophers, as well as some scientists, have asked (at least implicitly) is this: What should be regarded as ultimate or basic evidence? In other words, what is our evidential bedrock? This question might seem strange at first. Clearly, it is information about the world and what is happening in it that should serve as the ultimate evidence to be used in the construction and confirmation of our empirical theories. For example, a physician’s observation that her patient exhibits Koplik spots is (a piece of) the ultimate evidence for her diagnosis that the patient has the measles. Or, to take another example, my gas gauge’s needle position is my evidence for the belief that I have enough gas in the tank to get home easily. In light of these examples, it would seem that ordinary observations of the world, along with measurements, constitute our basic evidence.

      The same point is perhaps even more obvious in the example involving my gas gauge. Clearly, I need to know what the instrument is supposed to show before I can use the needle position as evidence for any hypotheses about the amount of gas left in my car, and thus as evidence for being able to get home safely. (Many of us have probably experienced confusion about a brand-new car’s instrumentation.) Furthermore, I already need to know what roles needles play in an instrument, and even what instruments in general are, viz., measuring devices of various kinds. None of this information can be gleaned directly from what we actually observe: distributions of colors, surfaces, and the like.

      Considerations such as these have led many to propose that the ultimate, or basic, evidence for all of our hypotheses about the world are various distributions of colors, edges, sounds, and the like, which result from impacts of the world on our sense organs. As the American philosopher Willard van Orman Quine famously put it:

      “[…] the only information that can reach our sensory surfaces from external objects must be limited to two-dimensional optical projections and various impacts of air waves and some gaseous reactions in the nasal passages and a few kindred odds and ends. How […] could one hope to find out about that external world from such meager traces?”

      (Roots of Reference, 1974, 2)

      2.2.2 Causes and Evidence

      The main issue with the view that the ultimate evidence consists in features within a person’s sensory field is that it seems highly unnatural. Clearly, I don’t seem to observe edges and colors and only then form, by some unknown process, beliefs about my environment. I don’t seem to first see rectangularly shaped red patches supported by a shiny, gray surface and then infer that there are books with red covers in my old metal bookcase. I seem to see the books and the bookcase themselves, directly, as it were. If someone were to ask me why I believe that my books are still in my bookcase, I would certainly say something like, “Because I can see them,” rather than, “Because this particular distribution of red rectangles on a shiny gray surface is good evidence for the presence of my books in the bookcase.” And yet, it is of course correct to say that seeing the red rectangles on a gray surface is involved in my belief that the books are still there.

      In order to resolve this tension, we need to make a distinction between a description of the processes by which we become aware of our environment and the question as to what counts as evidence for what. Cognitive science tells us that our beliefs about the world stem from stimulations of various sense organs, which are then processed by our brain and result eventually in beliefs about what’s out there. However, this process from sensory stimulations to beliefs is not obviously the same as the grounding of our beliefs on evidence. Reflecting the ordinary ways in which we talk about evidence, we will adhere for our purposes to a distinction between causal and evidential relations. The path from sensory stimulations to beliefs about the world consists in a long chain of causal links. To correctly describe and understand this causal chain is the task of cognitive science. The task of the philosophy of science is to isolate those elements in the causal chain that stand in an evidential relation to the relevant beliefs.