Autonomy. Beate Roessler. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Beate Roessler
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Афоризмы и цитаты
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781509538010
Скачать книгу
problem, see Peter Goldie, The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotions, and the Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 76‒97.

      31 31 Cf. Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar’s detailed and informative “Introduction: Autonomy Refigured,” in Mackenzie and Stoljar (eds), Relational Autonomy, 3‒34. Here again we can see parallels between the philosophical traditions as the idea of relational autonomy can also be found (if not in these words) in Habermas. Cf. Jürgen Habermas, “Individuation Through Socialization: An Essay on George Herbert Mead’s Theory of Subjectivity,” Postmetaphysical Thinking: Philosophical Essays (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992), 149‒204; and Seyla Benhabib, “The Generalized and the Concrete Other: The Kohlberg‒Gilligan Controversy and Moral Theory,” Situating the Self: Gender, Community, and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics (New York: Routledge, 1992), 148‒77; as well as the passage in Hobbes in which he compares men to mushrooms springing up out of the earth “without all kind of engagement to each other.”

      32 32 Marilyn Friedman clearly points to this in her critique of attempts to reduce autonomy to social conditions. Cf. Friedman, Autonomy, Gender, Politics, 81‒115. Friedman, like Diana Meyers, argues that autonomy is relational, weakly substantial, gradually attributable, and not dependent on a completely harmonious and uniform self. I return to all of these – plausible – aspects of autonomy below. Cf. Diana Tietjen Meyers, “Intersectional Identity and the Authentic Self? Opposites Attract!,” in Catriona Mackenzie and Natalie Stoljar (eds), Relational Autonomy, 151‒80.

      33 33 Cf. Paul Benson, “Free Agency and Self-Worth,” Journal of Philosophy 91(12) (1994): 650‒68 (660f.). John Rawls, although not an avowed theorist of autonomy, declares self-respect to be “perhaps the most important primary good” for individual liberty, without which nothing seems worth the effort. Cf. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 1999 [1971]), 348. See also Joel Anderson and Axel Honneth, “Autonomy, Vulnerability, Recognition, and Justice,” in John Christman and Joel Anderson (eds), Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism, 127‒49.

      34 34 Cf. Catriona Mackenzie, “Relational Autonomy, Normative Authority and Perfectionism,” Journal of Social Philosophy 39 (2008): 512‒33.

      35 35 Marina Oshana, Personal Autonomy in Society (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006). See also chapter 8 below on the question of whether (or in what ways) autonomy is also possible under non-liberal political conditions. Cf. also Martha Nussbaum, “Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism,” Political Theory 20(2) (1992): 202‒46.

      36 36 Axel Honneth argues that individuals must be intersubjectively connected in order to be autonomous. Cf. Honneth, “Decentered Autonomy,” 192. See also Christoph Menke, “Autonomy and Liberation,” as well as chapter 8 below.

      37 37 These two elements figure prominently in Christman’s The Politics of Persons and have also been adopted by other authors including Mackenzie, Stoljar, and Betzler.

      38 38 As Rawls, for example, describes in A Theory of Justice, 358‒65.

      39 39 Ian McEwan, Solar (New York: Anchor Books, 2010), 261f.

      Vorrei e non vorrei; mi trema un poco il cor.

      (Zerlina, Don Giovanni)

      “Neurotic, ha!” I let out a scornful laugh. “If neurotic is wanting two mutually exclusive things at one and the same time, then I’m neurotic as hell. I’ll be flying back and forth between one mutually exclusive thing and another for the rest of my days.”1

      Autonomy can fail in a number of ways, and ambivalence is one of them. We have just seen that an action is autonomous when the person acting has reflected on her (often conflicting) desires, motivations, beliefs, and feelings and has made a decision according to her own reasons. If ambivalence means being too uncertain to be able to make a decision, or repeatedly questioning a decision already made, then certainly it represents a danger. This is why ambivalence and indecisiveness are frequently conceived of as threats to autonomy in contemporary theories of autonomy and action.

      We also have to deal with different forms of ambivalence in our everyday lives where we are confronted with a variety of conflicts of identity that can be directly tied to ambivalent decision-making.3 Cultural identity conflicts play a role here, as do conflicting role requirements, which can make it extremely difficult if not impossible for a person to make clear-cut decisions. Marya Schechtman offers the example of an attorney who has to attend an important partner meeting but also wants to go to her daughter’s ballet recital.4

      Does all this mean that most of us mostly do not act autonomously? That seems highly implausible and problematic. The relation between autonomy and ambivalence must therefore be analyzed more precisely – particularly if we are interested in a concept of autonomy that can be used to explain and interpret autonomy in daily life and that can be understood as a prerequisite of a meaningful, well-lived life. In what follows, I will first expound the concept of ambivalence and its origins, then distinguish between different forms of ambivalence that pose different kinds of threats. I will then discuss more or less plausible theories for explaining ambivalence and dedicate myself to the question of how complex the concept of an ambivalent self needs to be.

      What is the claim that I want to defend? That appropriately coping with ambivalence need not be conceived of as a threat to autonomy, that ambivalence should rather be understood as an expression of the complexity of the self, of a rational relationship to conflicts of desires, beliefs, roles, and identities, and finally of the contingencies of everyday life. A person is thus autonomous precisely when she can deal with her ambivalences in a self-determined way.

      But as part of this initial overview, let us also look at other forms of ambivalence that are not necessarily immediately paralyzing. For in contemporary discourse surrounding autonomy and action theory, ambivalence is also used in a broader sense to refer not only to conflicting feelings toward a single object or person but also to conflicting desires, motivations, and potential actions. Some approaches to the phenomenon of ambivalence even include all forms of uncertainty in decision-making, such as the problem