The Philosopher's Toolkit. Julian Baggini. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Julian Baggini
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Афоризмы и цитаты
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781119103233
Скачать книгу
premises.

      Philosophers who object to infinite regresses of justification and who find in the coherentist vision just vicious circularity often look for something fundamental or foundational, a stopping point or bedrock for reasons and justification. Philosophers of this sort are often called foundationalists. There must be for foundationalists premises that stand in need of no further justification through other arguments. Let’s call them ‘basic premises’.

      There’s been a lot of ink spilled about what are to count as basic premises and why they are basic. By some accounts (called contextualist), the local context in which one is reasoning determines what’s basic. For example, a basic premise might be, ‘I exist’. In most contexts, this premise does not stand in need of justification. But if, of course, the argument is trying to demonstrate that I exist, my existence cannot be used as a premise. One cannot assume what one is trying to argue for.

      Other kinds of philosophers have held that certain sentences are more or less basic for other reasons: because they are based upon self‐evident or ‘cataleptic’ perceptions (stoics), because they are directly rooted in sense data (positivists), because they are grasped by a power called intuition or insight (Platonists), because they make up the framework of any possible inquiry and therefore cannot themselves be the objects of inquiry (Kantians, Wittgensteinians), because they are revealed to us by God (theologians), or because we grasp them using cognitive faculties certified by God (Cartesians).

      Other philosophers, principally sceptics, have challenged the idea that an ultimate ground can be given at all for reasoning. Appeals to neither (1) regresses, nor (2) circles, nor (3) foundations ultimately work. The problem is an old one and has been popularly described as ‘Agrippa’s trilemma’. See Graeco‐Roman Diogenes Laëritus’s Lives of Eminent Philosophers (9.88–89) and Sextus Empiricus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism (PH 1.15.164) for the details.

      SEE ALSO

      1 1.10 Definitions

      2 3.7 Circularity

      3 7.1 Basic beliefs

      4 7.9 Self‐evident truths

      READING

       * Nigel Warburton (2000). Thinking From A to Z, 2nd edn

       John Shand (2000). Arguing Well

       * Graham Priest (2001). Logic: A Very Short Introduction

       Peter Klein (2008). ‘Contemporary responses to Agrippa’s trilemma' in The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism (ed. John Greco)

      The murder was clearly premeditated, Watson. The only person who knew where Dr Fishcake would be that night was his colleague, Dr Salmon. Therefore, the killer must be …

      Deduction is the form of reasoning that is often emulated in the formulaic drawing‐room denouements of classic detective fiction. It is the most rigorous form of argumentation there is, since in deduction the move from premises to conclusions is such that if the premises are true, then the conclusion must (necessarily) also be true. For example, take the following argument:

      1 Elvis Presley lives in a secret location in Idaho.

      2 All people who live in secret locations in Idaho are miserable.

      3 Therefore, Elvis Presley is miserable.

      If we look at our definition of a deduction, we can see how this argument fits the bill. If the two premises are true, then the conclusion must also definitely be true. How could it not be true that Elvis is miserable, if it is indeed true that all people who live in secret locations in Idaho are miserable, and Elvis is one of those people?

      The question of what makes a good deductive argument is addressed in more detail in the section on validity and soundness (1.4). But in a sense, everything that you need to know about a deductive argument is contained within the definition just given: a (successful) deductive argument is one where, if the premises are true, then the conclusion is definitely true.

      Before we leave this topic, however, we should return to the investigations pursued by our detective. Reading his deliberations, one could easily insert the vital, missing words. The killer must surely be Dr Salmon. But is this the conclusion of a successful deductive argument? The fact is that we can’t answer this question unless we know a little more about the exact meaning of the premises.

      First, what does it mean to say the murder was ‘premeditated’? It could mean lots of things. It could mean that it was planned right down to the last detail, or it could mean simply that the murderer had worked out what she would do in advance. If it is the latter, then it is possible that the murderer did not know where Dr Fishcake would be that night, but, coming across him by chance, put into action her premeditated plan to kill him. So, it could be the case (1) that both premises are true (the murder was premeditated, and Dr Salmon was the only person who knew where Dr Fishcake would be that night) but (2) that the conclusion is false (Dr Salmon is, in fact, not the murderer). Therefore, the detective has not formed a successful deductive argument.

      SEE ALSO

      1 1.1 Arguments, premises, and conclusions

      2 1.3 Induction

      3 1.4 Validity and soundness

      READING

       *