Adam Smith. Craig Smith. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Craig Smith
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Историческая литература
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781509518265
Скачать книгу
that despite the wide variety of behaviour we find in different cultures, there is a shared basic model of human psychology. This means that no one form of social life is any more ‘natural’ than any other, and so crude ethnocentric judgements are to be avoided. The point is not that some societies are defective or corrupted according to some crude normative scale, but rather that they need to be understood in their own terms. The commitment to a universal human nature has several further implications for Smith’s thinking. Smith, unlike some of his fellow Scots, is uninterested in ideas of race or polygenesis: all human beings are the same in his view. More generally, the thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment also had to defend the idea of a universal human nature from the possibility that human behaviour was directly affected by the physical environment. In the Spirit of the Laws, Montesquieu had detailed experiments with heat and cold that purported to show that the climate had a direct effect on human physical responsiveness. This could then be used to explain why different parts of the globe displayed different behaviour. David Hume, in the essay ‘Of National Characters’, systematically destroyed this theory and demonstrated that differences in behaviour between different social groups are due to social factors rather than differences in climate. The differences between the French and the Germans cannot be explained by radically different climates, nor do geographically dispersed people such as the Jews differ radically in the practices they maintain.

      Second, the descriptive account of different types of society need not be understood as deterministic and inevitable. Smith is not saying that all societies will inevitably pass through the four stages. Indeed, he is explicit that there are examples of mixed forms of society, of societies that have moved from hunting to agriculture without being shepherds, and even that there are societies that have been commercial and are now agricultural. Lived history does not fit neatly onto the model being developed here, but that does not diminish the accession of knowledge that the science of man acquires by thinking about societies in this way. Even if we had a complete historical record of a particular society’s development through time, and that record did not conform to the conjectural speculations, this would in no way discredit the approach. As Dugald Stewart observed, the systematic knowledge advances our understanding of the general phenomenon of society as such.

      Rousseau had adopted a deliberately contrarian attitude to the Enlightenment notions of reason, science, and progress. In his Discourse and elsewhere, he made the case that the development of modern civilization was not an example of progress but rather a tale of the corruption of humanity from an original innocence to a selfish and vanity-driven modernity. Rousseau’s account dwelt on the idea that the process of socialization had created perverted value systems grounded in envy and self-conceit, where pride and concern for social status had transformed humanity for the worse. As Smith rightly noted, Rousseau’s idea was very similar to that of Mandeville, who had extended his original satirical poem about a beehive, which charted the beneficial unintended consequences of selfish behaviour (burglars make work for locksmiths), into a theory of morality that reduced moral behaviour to a desire for social approbation and an aversion to social embarrassment (the moral virtues are flattery begot on pride). Mandeville’s conclusion that private vices created public benefits signals an issue that clearly came to fascinate Smith: what happens when intentions and outcomes do not obviously cohere?

      These ideas are interesting because they provide us with the initial jumping-off point of the Moral Sentiments. Rousseau and Mandeville had focused on how a set of shared beliefs and institutions could emerge from social interaction: for Rousseau, the result was a moral abomination and a deeply corrupted society; for Mandeville, the result was the cynical realization of the unintended generation of wealth and power. Smith had before him a mode of explanation that promised to allow a scientific, evolutionary, and naturalistic account of how human moral practice emerged as an unintended consequence of social life, but he also had before him two quite different conclusions about whether this was necessarily a good thing.