The Case for Universal Basic Services. Anna Coote. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Anna Coote
Издательство: John Wiley & Sons Limited
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Экономика
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781509539840
Скачать книгу
necessities but about adopting a set of value-based guidelines and customizing them to suit a variety of different needs and circumstances.

      The term UBS was first given voice in October 2017 in a report from the Institute for Global Prosperity, University College London.2 It offers an approach that is distinct from ‘universal basic income’ (UBI). The latter is a proposal to give regular, unconditional cash payments to everyone, rich and poor – ostensibly to reduce poverty and inequality, promote opportunities and solve problems arising from ungenerous, stigmatizing systems of income support. We wholeheartedly endorse the principle that everyone should have the right to a minimum income and that no one should suffer blame or stigma for falling on hard times. Radical reform of income support, although not the topic of this book, is extremely urgent. But the solution to the problem of inadequate social security is not ‘UBI’, universal, unconditional cash payments that are sufficient to live on, which is how it is defined by many of its leading advocates. We can find no evidence that UBI could ever live up to the more ambitious claims that are made for it.3

      1 1. A formal definition of a ‘service’, as distinct from a ‘good’, is a type of activity that is intangible, is not stored, does not result in ownership and is used at the point of delivery.

      2 2. Social Prosperity Network (2017), ‘Social Prosperity for the Future: A Proposal for Universal Basic Services’, UCL: IGP.

      3 3. A. Coote and E. Yazici (2019), ‘Universal Basic Income: A Briefing for Trade Unions’, Ferney-Voltaire, France: Public Services International.

      No one should have to pay for emergency health care or endure a three-week wait to see a local doctor. Every parent should feel confident that their children will be happy and well educated at the local (non-fee-paying) school. There should be no need for food banks or rough sleeping, no graphs showing widening health inequalities or rising levels of mental distress.

      When the United Nations sent a Special Rapporteur on Extreme Poverty and Human Rights to the United States in 2017, he found that none of its manifestly superior wealth, power and technology was being ‘harnessed to address the situation in which 40 million people continue to live in poverty’. He concluded that the persistence of extreme poverty was ‘a political choice made by those in power’.1 When the same Rapporteur visited the United Kingdom in 2018, he found, similarly, that it was ‘patently unjust and contrary to British values’ that so many people were living in poverty in the world’s fifth-largest economy; it was not an inevitable consequence of economic forces, he said, but the choice of a government committed to ‘radical social re-engineering’.2 The United States and the United Kingdom may have moved further in this direction than other rich countries, but there have been comparable shifts in government priorities, public attitudes and spending patterns across the rich world.

      All human beings have the same set of basic needs that must be satisfied in order to survive and thrive, think for ourselves and participate in society. Theories of capability and human need converge around this point. Martha Nussbaum describes three ‘core’ capabilities: of affiliation, bodily integrity and practical reason.3 Len Doyal and Ian Gough identify health and critical autonomy as basic human needs that are prerequisites for social participation.4

      Needs are not like wants. Wants vary infinitely and can multiply exponentially. If you don’t get what you want, you won’t die or cease to be part of human society, but that could happen if you don’t get what you need. Needs cannot usually be substituted for one another (a lack of water and shelter cannot be offset by more education or health care). They are part of an essential package. And needs are satiable: there are limits beyond which more food, more work or more security are no longer helpful and could even do you harm. There comes a point where sufficiency is reached in the process of meeting needs. By contrast, there will never come a time when we all have everything we want.

      As individuals today, we can meet some of our needs through market transactions, depending on our circumstances. Food and clothing are examples here: most of us expect to be able to buy these ourselves, and having enough money to do this is clearly important. There are other needs that most of us cannot meet without help and we depend on others for our capacity to do so. Health care and education are the most common examples but, as we shall argue, the range of needs requiring a collective response is much wider. If we are to live together in society, we are all responsible for ensuring that everyone’s basic needs are met – through a combination of measures to support income and provide services. As the sociologist Emile Durkheim observed, people ‘cannot live together without agreeing and consequently without making mutual sacrifices, joining themselves to one another in a strong and enduring fashion’. This is not just a worthy option, but the ‘fundamental basis’ of social life.7