Free Speech Law and the Pornography Debate. Lynn Mills Eckert. Читать онлайн. Newlib. NEWLIB.NET

Автор: Lynn Mills Eckert
Издательство: Ingram
Серия:
Жанр произведения: Юриспруденция, право
Год издания: 0
isbn: 9781498572613
Скачать книгу
in the culture as best we can understand it or lose respect.[21] Some groups experience the potential for regulation as threatening and retrogressive while others understand potential regulation as a commitment to equality. Can epistemology help us to navigate through the debate?

      Epistemology and the Law: Content-Neutrality, Causality, and Discursive Effects

      What does this understanding of epistemology specifically entail for my analysis of law and pornography? It means that the first step in my attempt to understand the pornography debate in US law will be to ask a series of questions closer to a sociology-of-knowledge approach. What makes it possible for pornography to exist in the inegalitarian form and to thrive? What institutions, structures, rules, beliefs, discourses, and ideologies must be in place to justify and defend inegalitarian pornography? What conditions would need to change in order to understand it differently and perhaps for it to transform? In essence, the first step is to bracket the moral claims about the rightness or wrongness of pornography regulations and determine whether we regulate pornography and, if we do, how and why?

      The sociology-of-knowledge approach yields important insights about how and why we regulate porn and what law is willing or unwilling to say about it. Interestingly, in the modern era, law rarely uses obscenity to regulate porn but instead draws upon zoning law. Those different regulative approaches (obscenity, zoning, civil damage approaches) apply varying categorical choices, concepts, and language. One chapter will examine the varying categorical choices in both the zoning and civil damage cases regulating pornography, analyzing their implications for regulations. Another chapter will linger on the language used to describe adult establishments and nude dancing, to uncover the banal meanings hidden from us due to our familiarity.

      After examining the categorical choices and language of the zoning and nude dancing cases, the next chapter analyzes free speech doctrine itself. Specifically, I will examine the assumptions underlying a core element of modern free speech doctrine, namely, the content-neutrality principle. The content-neutrality principle holds that government may never regulate speech based upon a like or dislike of the message. The guiding purpose of the principle is to prevent government from making a judgment about speech: its rightness or wrongness. Government can and should remain neutral in evaluating speech in our democracy. This indeed is a noble principle, one worth preserving. Yet, intentions that inform the categories of law sometimes deviate from how those categorizations operate in practice. I will argue that content-neutrality in practice is non-neutral when it comes to evaluating the harms from pornography and hate speech. An espistemological approach described earlier in the introduction will help us to understand how and why the current understanding of content-neutrality is profoundly biased.

      More specifically, I will explore how the content-neutrality principle effectively functions as both a gender and racially coded category, preventing any serious evaluation of harm claims stemming from speech that implicates Fourteenth Amendment concerns. Instead of upholding values of neutrality in assessing such inegalitarian forms of speech, content-neutrality functions in an ahistorical and acontextual manner, stripping away the ability to assess meaning and negative effects from language. As we know, harm remains one of the principal rationales to constitutionally regulate speech under US free speech doctrine. If speech harms, as in the case of libel, we regulate. Language, its meaning and effects, is deeply contextual, depending upon power, history, and culture. Any process that prohibits a weighing of such factors operates in a de facto non-neutral manner.

      Embedded in modern free speech doctrine and its central tenet, the content-neutrality principle, is a particular understanding of speech that I will examine as well. Despite advances in philosophy about the nature of language and how it shapes our reality, free speech doctrine remains mired in a libertarian understanding of speech. The classic colloquial description of that perspective is embodied in the old children’s saying “sticks and stones may break my bones but names will never hurt me.” In this view, speech is distinctive from the real world of action. Yet poststructural theory provides an alternative understanding of speech through the concept of discursive effects. Following from that view, discourse creates more than hurt feelings. Instead, it generates ideological, material, and epistemic effects. The very concept of discursive effects challenges not only the libertarian understanding of speech but also dislodges the causal criteria to prove harm. Under the civil damage ordinance approach advocated by Catharine MacKinnon and Andrea Dworking in American Booksellers v. Hudnut (1985), the content-neutrality principle would not prevent government from regulating pornography if harm could be causally proven. Yet, in Hudnut, pro-regulation advocates find themselves in a catch-22: to narrowly define the kind of porn that harms is to reference its gendered, misogynistic, and violent content. Once the definition references content, it triggers the content-neutrality principle. If the content-neutrality principle is operative, the only way to prove harm is causally. Under a theory of discursive effects, speech produces serious effects or harms about which egalitarian liberals should be concerned, but not in a causal manner. Causality, as Foucault tells us, is a mystification: an unattainable ideal beyond the grasp of even the hard sciences.

      While the concept of discursive effects may better explain how porn harms than sophisticated causal accounts or speech-act theory, the fact remains that law is conservative in its reliance on precedent. Free speech precedent in cases involving pornography regulation (and hate speech) does not rely upon a poststructural understanding of speech or discursive effects.[22] Instead, I will contend, arguments that present courts with harm claims about pornographic speech (or hate speech) rely upon precedents that invoke outdated understandings of speech. Yet the claim I wish to make in the pages that follow is that we must re-read a seminal case, Brown v. Board of Education (1954), through the lens of speech and, specifically, from the framework of discursive effects. Such a re-reading depends upon Charles Lawrence’s radical re-interpretation of Brown as a case primarily about speech. Lawrence argues that the expressive elements inhering in the practice of segregation (i.e., the message of white supremacy) harms more than the actual act of segregating individuals. The sting, humiliation, and harm from segregation is expressive, particularly in instances where the pro-segregation advocates attempted to provide equal facilities, eliminating the potential for facial discrimination.[23] I want to extend Charles Lawrence’s profound and ground-breaking insight about Brown as speech, placing it within the context of discursive effects. Lawrence, in his argument, highlights Warren’s concerns about the effects of segregation on the hearts and minds of young black children. For Lawrence, those effects are the harms from a white supremacist message. Those harms, in my view, are better understood as discursive effects. In Lawrence’s re-reading of Brown we see the very linguistic turn in philosophy mentioned at the beginning of the introduction. Segregation becomes a discursive problematic, the social construction of meaning, and it is accorded density and weight.[24]

      With the concept of discursive effects, we have a more extensive understanding of how discursive practices effect or hurt “the hearts and minds” of young black children and we have a better ability to understand the extent of those harms on citizenship outside of the confining and distorting frame of causality. Reframed from the lens of discursive effects, Warren’s moving language in Brown is describing the ideological, material, and epistemic effects of a white supremacist message. The mechanism of those devastating harms is not causal and they do not, I will argue, rest upon speech-act theory.

      If Lawrence is correct and Brown should be properly understood as speech, then I hope to utilize that radical reinterpretation in two ways. First, I want to suggest that embedded in US law are arguments, however brief or momentary, that may be recouped, highlighted, and reapplied to incorporate an understanding of harmful speech of the kind in inegalitarian pornography by deploying the concept of discursive effects. Such an understanding of harmful speech in terms of discursive effects, I will contend, is compatible with US law and its liberal philosophical foundations. By connecting discursive effects to a well-established precedent (Brown), it is possible to avert concerns about the conservative nature of precedent. In effect, a new paradigm of discursive effects helps us to better understand a case long ago decided and more effectively elucidates the precise reasons why expression helped to maintain inequality in the case of segregation in violation of the Fourteenth Amendment.