Egypt: Rogers also makes much of the claim in Augustus’s autobiography that he had added Egypt “…to the imperium of the Roman people.” (Aug. R.G., 27.) Why not again to the Roman Senate and People, SPQR? The omission of the “Senate” here is significant, but not for the reason that Rogers suggests. Augustus is certainly not claiming to have handed Egypt over to one of the popular assemblies. Egypt was newly conquered from Cleopatra (allied to Mark Antony), and Augustus ruled it as part of his own patrimonium (private estate) because he did not want the Senate or any senator to gain control of this rich province. So, the governor of Egypt was never a senator but always an equestrian with the title of “prefect”, and no senator was allowed even to set foot in Egypt without express imperial consent. How was Augustus to publicize his acquisition of Egypt in his autobiography? He could not very well say, “I added Egypt to my own private estate.” And he also did not want to say that he had given it to the Roman Senate and People, because then the Senate could have gotten its hands on it. So, he just said that he had added it to the imperium, of the Roman people. The term imperium in this context belongs to the category of what Lewis and Short call “publicists’ language,” with the multiple meanings of “supreme power, sovereignty, sway, dominion, and empire.” (Lewis and Short, s.v. imperium.) This had nothing to do with the popular assemblies but was simply a vague propaganda claim that Egypt was now under Roman control and the “people” certainly never had any say over Egypt or over who was to govern it.
“Ironic victory”: Rogers suggests that:
[I]t is possible to argue” that the Augustan “monarchy itself was one of the (unintended) consequences of the struggle between some of the nobiles and the populus Romanus over the question of who was the sovereign power in the res publica. If we look at the breakdown of the Roman Republic from this perspective, we might see the emergence of a monarch from among the nobiles in 27 BC as an ironic victory for that democratic element in the Roman constitution, the Roman people. (Millar 2002, loc. 206.)
This is muddled. The fall of the Roman Republic was indeed the victory over the senatorial aristocracy by the people’s champion, first Julius Caesar and then his heir, Augustus. But it makes little sense to suggest that this amounted to the victory of the “…democratic element in the Roman constitution, the Roman people.” Moreover, if the Roman people had exercised as much power in the Republic as Millar and Rogers seem to believe, why would they have wanted to destroy the Republic? Yet Julius Caesar had made no bones about his contempt for the Republic by accepting an indefinite dictatorship and by describing the Republic as just “…a name without substance or form.” Augustus’s victory was not of democracy but of a form of monarchy that artfully concealed its true nature and managed to survive, with some modifications, for some 300 years.
Mommsen’s “Dyarchy”
The famous German historian Theodor Mommsen (1817–1903) believed the Augustan regime was a “dyarchy” or “diarchy”, in which power was shared between Augustus and the Senate. This view is not generally accepted. My own view, as mentioned above, is that what Augustus established was a monarchical regime based, as we have seen, on a combination of wide powers, with authority resting on broad support from the plebs, the equites, and the army, together with at least toleration by the surviving members of the Republican senatorial aristocracy and the support of the new men whom he had helped to qualify for entry into the Senate.
Syme: “A Monarchy Rules through an Oligarchy”
Against Millar’s rejection of the characterisation of the Roman Republic as either an aristocracy or an oligarchy, we have this important statement by Sir Ronald Syme about the Roman Republic, based on detailed prosopographical evidence: “In any age of the history of Republican Rome about twenty or thirty men, drawn from a dozen dominant families, hold a monopoly of office and power.” (Syme 1939, p. 124.) In his much acclaimed The Roman Revolution, a book about the rise to power of Augustus, written in 1939, Syme portrayed Augustus as an autocrat in all but name. But then Syme went off at a tangent and proclaimed in ringing tones, without any evidential basis that “In all ages, whatever the form and name of government or whatever may be the name and theory of the constitution, be it monarchy, republic, or democracy, an oligarchy lurks behind the façade.” (1939, 7, 15.) Fifty years later, in 1989, his portrayal of Augustus’s regime was still the same, describing it as “autocratic government” and adding; “The Princeps duly went on to exploit the ‘res publica’, encroaching on the functions of Senate, of magistrates, of laws.” And:“‘Potentia’ now assumed the respectable name of ‘auctoritas’.” (Syme 1989, p. 1 f.)
I agree with Syme on the monopoly of office and power in the Roman Republic, but I certainly do not agree with the application of his one-size-fits-all oligarchic theory to the Augustan Principate. Accepting that Augustus initiated a monarchy, Syme tried to square the circle with the self-contradictory and erroneous oracular comment that “A monarchy rules through an oligarchy.”
Monarchy and oligarchy are diametric opposites, representing the two poles of governmental power. (See Chapter 6 for a full discussion.) By “monarchy,” I mean true, strong monarchy, a system in which power is concentrated in the hands of one person, usually with support from the lower classes, against the return of the oligarchy or aristocracy, which they have most likely overthrown. An oligarchy, on the other hand, is normally intent on perpetuating its shared group power and is, therefore, afraid of any one person becoming too powerful and having too much popular support. The vicissitudes of Roman history epitomize this type of conflict.
In the Res Gestae, as we have seen, Augustus makes a point of stating that he had no more potestas than any of his colleagues in office but surpassed everyone in auctoritas. (R.G. 34.5.) Auctoritas means “influence” and potestas refers to legally authorised, constitutional power. So, Augustus is trying to portray his position as conforming to the norms of the Republican constitution, which he claims to have restored. The fact that he had more auctoritas than anyone else was not unlawful. It was simply the expression of the esteem and prestige enjoyed by Augustus, similar to that which even great anti-monarchical Republican heroes of the past like Cincinnatus might have enjoyed. But what is potentia?
Syme does not mention potestas at all, but rather potentia and he does not suggest that this was ever given up, only that it masqueraded under the “respectable name of auctoritas.” Unlike potestas, which is duly authorised, constitutional power, and auctoritas, which was not power at all, potentia was unbridled, naked power or might.
Syme’s portrayal of Augustus is a gross exaggeration of Augustus’s position, but it is correct insofar as the regime is shown to be monarchical. Yet, no sooner does Syme condemn Augustus as a lawless despot than we come across the bombshell quoted above: “In all ages, whatever the form and name of government, be it monarchy, republic, or democracy, an oligarchy lurks behind the façade.” (Syme 1939, 7, 15.) Was Augustus’s rule not monarchical then? Syme certainly believed it was.